Skip to main content
Log in

The Problem of Truth in Quantum Mechanics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Global Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a large literature on the issue of the lack of properties (i.e. accidents) in quantum mechanics (the problem of “hidden variables”) and also on the indistinguishability of particles. Both issues were discussed as far back as the late 1920’s. However, the implications of these challenges to classical ontology were taken up rather late, in part in the ‘quantum set theory’ of Takeuti (Curr Issues Quant Logic 303–322, 1981), Finkelstein (in Beltrametti EG, Van Fraassen BC (eds) Current issues in quantum logic. Plenum, New York, 1981) and the work of Décio Krause (1992)—and subsequent publications). But the problems created by quantum mechanics go far beyond set theory or the identity of indiscernibles (another subject that has been often discussed)—it extends, I argue, to our accounts of truth. To solve this problem, i.e. to have an approach to truth that facilitates a transition from a classical to a quantum ontology one must have a unified framework for them both. This is done within the context of a pluralist view of truthmaking, where the truthmakers are unified in having a monoidal structure. The structure of the paper is as follows. After a brief introduction, the idea of a monoid is outlined (in Sect. 1) followed by a standard set of axioms that govern the truthmaker relation from elements of the monoid to the set of propositions. This is followed, in Sect. 2, by a discussion of how to have truthmakers for two kinds of necessities: tautologies and analytic truths. The next Sect. 3, then applies these ideas to quantum mechanics. It gives an account of quantum states and shows how these form a monoid. The final section then argues that quantum logic does not, despite what one might initially suspect, stand in the way of an account of quantum truth.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Moody (1953) p. 102. It has to be said that, strictly, this formulation does not say anything as to what the proposition signifies to be and it may just as well be how ideas relate to one another as what the states of affairs are, even if the latter are what one tends to think of as intended.

  2. This is not to say that Armstrong did not give a lot of space to necessary truths, including the mathematical, indeed he devoted a third of his book to the subject, chapters 7–10.

  3. In the Tractatus, all the 2 and 3 series of propositions, e.g. 2.173: ‘A picture represents its subject from a position outside it. (Its standpoint is its representational form.) That is why a picture represents its subject correctly or incorrectly.’ Also Tractatus 4.1: ‘Propositions represent the existence and non-existence of states of affairs’. This last could almost be a motto for this paper.

  4. For algebraic objects like groups and monoids, in fact associative algebras in general, there is a mathematical notion of representation where the algebra is represented by symmetries in a vector space (usually) [see Steinberg (2016), or for a general introduction Gowers (2009, IV.9) or Derksen and Weyman (2005)]. This is not quite the sense of ‘representation’ used above, but the underlying principle is the same: one structure is represented in a different structure. It cannot be ruled out that the fuller notion may enter into the picture in the future. Into which structure we make the representation is something that can be adjusted to purpose.

  5. Weyl acknowledges the prior work from 1900-1 of Edmund Husserl in the Logical Investigations, and Husserl there relied heavily on the idea of states of affairs. The publication of Weyl’s work was delayed by the war.

  6. Armstrong characterises the relationship between truthmakers in terms of mereology (and others have followed suit). But mereological fusion generates a monoid structure; thus we lose nothing in speaking of the latter notion, which is accepted algebra.

  7. Such an element is also called an absorbing element or an annihilating element—though this is only suggestive when the operation is analogous to multiplication. Wittgenstein also spoke of a ‘totality of facts’, at Tractatus 1.1.

  8. Wittgenstein (1921). However from the part relation one can also see that there is no sense in which all states of affairs can be regarded as independent or separate from one another—thus the Tractatus’ proposition 2.061 cannot be accepted: ‘States of affairs are independent of one another.’ But the complement to a state of affairs  s  could be said to be independent of  s .

  9. It has to be noted that Cameron is trying to square his view with Lewisian metaphysical claims, such as Humean Supervenience and this may have caused him to adopt an account of truthmaking which is different to that found in the authors mentioned in footnote 6 below.

  10. See Heathcote (2003). Many of these axioms go back in some form or other to Mulligan et al. (1984). See also Armstrong (2004) and Read (2000)—with useful clarification on half-disjunction in the latter paper. See  4 below. The same denial of a full disjunction thesis goes back to Aristotle in On Interpretation. With Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006, 2009), I reject a generalised entailment principle—for discussion see Jago (2009) and de Sa and Dan (2009).

  11. As long as we have a monoid with no negative elements we should not get paradox. It is reasonable to conjecture that contradictions such as the Liar paradox arise because there are negative elements in the truthmaker ground (in this case the monoid of sentences) as well as the objects (also the sentences) that we are mapping to. We leave this suggestive idea hanging.

  12. At 4,4611 he likens tautologies and contradictions to the symbol “0” of arithmetic. But this may strike us as odd—surely both can’t be analogous to the digit for zero.

  13. In fact Armstrong does embrace necessary states of affairs, as well as the addition of different kinds of truthmakers. His strategy could be described as pluralist—as was Wittgenstein’s. Armstrong’s strategy is to enlarge the set of truthmakers to include specific objects, such as numbers, but to construe these in a possibilist fashion [taking the lead from Hellman (1989)].

  14. If one puts this in terms of possible worlds: the particular truthmaker that makes the proposition true here may not obtain in another world, and so the proposition as a whole will be made true by a different truthmaker, say that of Socrates being alive, or Paris being in the Netherlands.

  15. This is notable as Armstrong wishes to explain arithmetic by postulating natural numbers as truthmakers for arithmetic truths. [see Armstrong (2004), pp. 96–104] In effect this would have been to postulate another monoidal model.

  16. Cf. Armstrong (2004) §8.9 where a meaning equivalence view is sketched. For more on the relation of the meaning interpretation to the present view see Heathcote (2018).

  17. It is interesting to note that this view of the experimental character of the a priori appears also to have been the view of C. S. Peirce.

    It has long been a puzzle how it could be that, on the one hand, mathematics is purely deductive in its nature, and draws its conclusions apodictically, while on the other hand, it presents as rich and apparently unending a series of surprising discoveries as any observational science. Various have been the attempts to solve the paradox by breaking down one or other of these assertions, but without success. The truth, however, appears to be that all deductive reasoning, even simple syllogism, involves an element of observation; namely, deduction consists in constructing an icon or diagram the relations of whose parts shall present a complete analogy with those of the parts of the object of reasoning, of experimenting upon this image in the imagination, and of observing the result so as to discover unnoticed and hidden relations among the parts (Peirce 1885, p. 182).

  18. It may be problematic for a quite different reason but I come to that shortly.

  19. The phrase echoes a similar comment in von Neumann’s article on the nature of mathematics, in his (1947). ‘I think that it is a relatively good approximation to truth—which is much too complicated to allow anything but approximations—that mathematical ideas originate in empirics, although the genealogy is sometimes long and obscure. But once they are so conceived, the subject begins to live a peculiar life of its own . . .’

  20. To be clear: the following argument is not that set theory is not ever available or applicable: it is that it is not always available. In particular, it is not available when we are considering the fundamental particles of physics.

  21. What I am outlining here is often called the Received View. This is not to say that there has not been push back against it, for example Muller (2015); Dorato and Morganti (2013); Bueno (2014) among others. In fact French and Krause (2006), though they discuss the Received View, do not entirely hold to it: they believe that QM is underdetermined by the evidence and that it can also support a view of particles as individuals. For pushback against the pushback, see Huggett and Norton (2013) and Heathcote (2020, 2021, 2021b).

  22. In Armstrong (2004) the basic form of a state of affairs is  a  ’s being  F —a way some thing is. See also Armstrong (1997). This of course comes from Wittgenstein.

  23. Here is one such argument that appeared originally in Fraassen et al. (2008) p. 23. Suppose you have a set  S  containing three indistinguishable particles. Then what it means for the cardinality of that set to have a cardinality of three is that there is a function  f  from the entities of  S  to the ordinal set \(\{ 0, 1, 2 \}\) but then \(f^{-1} (0) \ne f^{-1} (1) \ne f^{-1} (2)\) : thus the entities of  S  are distinguishable after all. The cardinality of the set seems unquestionable: three electrons have three times the mass and charge of one, so what must be rejected is the existence of the function to the ordinals. Applying this problem to Sher’s model-theoretic concept we can see that it manifests in the requirement that we have a function which orders entities in sequences: such sequences being required in the definition of satisfaction of a formula. These sequences are functions mapping a set of entities to ordinals—precisely what we have seen reason to doubt.

  24. The problem that indistinguishability creates for set theory has been studied over a number of years beginning with Parker-Rhodes (1981) Takeuti (1981); Finkelstein (1981); and then the papers Dalla Chiara et al. (1985, 1995); Schlesinger (1999), and nearly simultaneously Da Costa and Krause (1994), Krause (1992), Da Costa and Krause (1994, 1999); Krause and Arenhart (2018). More papers can be found in the reference sections of these articles.

  25. This account of states was given in Weyl (1931) and Von Neumann (1932)—in both cases the ideas were first developed in 1927 in German publications—and have been given in many textbook accounts since, for example Emch (1984), Takhtajan (2000) or Bengtsson and Życzkowski (2017). A notable account was also given in Husimi (1940). See also Mielnik (2012). The Hilbert space gives a representation space to the pure states of \(\mathscr {S}\) but not to the mixed states and thus from early on came, to some, to seem anomalous and possibly unnecessary. It was done away with in I. E. Segal’s more general set of postulates for quantum theory. There are non-realist views of the states but here we take a realist view.

  26. It is self-adjoint as a consequence of being positive.

  27. It would be possible, and perhaps more desirable, to build up the set of states \(\mathscr {S}\) simply from a locally convex, Hausdorff, topological vector space since the Krein-Milman theorem states that if we have \(\mathcal {C}\), a compact convex set of elements of such a space, then \(\mathcal {C}\) is the convex hull of its extreme points \(\mathcal {P}\) (Krein and Milman 1940). This generalises the original theorem of Minkowski to infinite dimensional topological vector spaces. (If the space is Hausdorff but not locally convex, then the theorem does not go through.) Likewise there is a partial converse due to Milman: suppose A is a compact subset of a locally convex topological space and the closed compact hull \(\mathcal {C}\) of  A  is compact then all the extreme points of \(\mathcal {C}\) are in  A  [see (Schaefer 1971, p. 67)].

  28. This implies that the set of states \(\mathscr {S}\) is, in addition to the above, a self-dual convex set. Duality (or topological duality), means that there is a convex set \(\mathscr {S} ^{*}\) such that there is an inner product \(<\, ,>\) defined on \(\mathscr {S}\) and \(\mathscr {S} ^{*}\), which is positive.

    $$\begin{aligned} \mathscr {S} ^{*} = \{ \sigma : \forall \rho \in \mathscr {S}, <\sigma \, , \rho >\;\, \ge 0 \}. \end{aligned}$$

    Self-duality then implies:

    $$\begin{aligned} \mathscr {S} ^{*}\; =\; \mathscr {S}. \end{aligned}$$

    States, as Penrose once noted, can be regarded as the square root of a probability. The self-duality of \(\mathscr {S}\) seems fit to formulate that idea (see Bengtsson and Życzkowski (2017), ch. 8.6, for more on this).

  29. Apart from the real, complex and quaternionic Hermitian operators there are Jordan algebras called Spin Factors \(J_{2} V_{n}\) that use a Minkowski metric and whose positive cones are the future light cones in a Minkowski space of dimension \(n + 1\). These appeared already in the original classification of Jordan et al. (1934).

  30. Jordan Banach algebras are the proper analog in the operator algebra domain.

  31. Weyl stated these relations but Von Neumann then proved them in his (1932, ch. VI).

  32. For incisive criticisms of this proposal, see Dummett (1978) or Maudlin (2005).

  33. Notice that there are exceptional cases where disjunction does distribute: for example where we have \(s \leadsto (A \vee A)\) then this reduces to just \(s \leadsto A\).

  34. The arguments above had been given in an earlier unpublished paper (by the present author) with an example which was not particularly good. But Read (2000) then came up with a better example and this is the one used in the text. It is interesting that this modal point was something neither Wittgenstein nor Russell considered. The preceding arguments were given in Heathcote (2003).

  35. Von Wright’s preface has it: ‘It was always thought that modality is akin to probability . . .Yet it was a surprise to me, when I first noted that a modal logic could be constructed which contains an analogue to the multiplication principle of probability theory.’ In von Neumann’s Collected Papers volume 4 there is a short mimeographed note from 1937 on ‘Quantum Logics (Strict and Probability Logics)’ that discusses the introduction of probability as a logical operator. See also Birkhoff (1958).

  36. The presence of the above suggestive analogy might make some philosophers wish that Birkhoff and von Neumann had given some attention to Hertz and Gentzen’s slightly earlier work on natural deduction systems as a model for their quantum logic, rather than the less obviously logical algebraic approach. Hermann Weyl, whose work we have already mentioned, was the doctoral advisor for Gentzen in the early 1930s; he tried, but failed, to get him to the IAS.

  37. It is worth noting in this context that von Neumann himself, when he came to the problem of constructing a quantificational generalisation of quantum logic—and therefor a system for multiple lattices in a tensor product—found it impossible, describing the difficulties, over years and after several serious attempts, as ‘exceedingly great’. This should give us more than momentary pause. See his letters written to F. B. Silsbee from 1944, in particular the letter of July 2\(^{\textrm{nd}}\) 1945 in Rédei (2005).

  38. If Wittgenstein or Russell had known of the idea of group representations which had come from Frobenius, Burnside and Schur they would have had a clearer model on which to formulate their nascent ideas.

References

  • Aerts D (1981) The one and the many: towards a unification of the quantum and classical description of one and many physical entities, Ph.D. Dissertation, Free University of Brussels

  • Aerts D (1982) Description of many separated physical entities without the paradoxes encountered in quantum mechanics. Found Phys 12(12):1131–1170

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Aerts D, Daubechies I (1978) Physical justification for using the tensor product to describe two quantum systems as one joint system. Helv Phys Acta 51(5–6):661–675

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (1989) A combinatorial theory of possibility. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (1997) A world of states of affairs. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (2004) Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aubrun G, Szarek SJ (2006) Tensor products of convex sets and the volume of separable states on N qudits. Phys Rev A 73:2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall JC (2000) On truthmakers for negative truths. Australas J Philos 78(2):264–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengtsson I, Życzkowski K (2017) Geometry of quantum states, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow JC (1976) Possible worlds foundations for probability. J Philos Log 5(3):299–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff G (1958) Von Neumann and lattice theory. Bull Am Math Soc 64(3):50–56

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff G, Von Neumann J (1936) The logic of quantum mechanics. Ann Math 37(4):823–843

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno O (2014) Why identity is fundamental. Am Philos Q 51:325–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron RP (2008) How to be a truthmaker maximalist. Noûs 42(3):410–21

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne C, Pigden C (2006) Negative truths from positive facts. Australas J Philos 84(2):249–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clifford AH, Preston GB (1964) The algebraic theory of semigroups, 2nd edn. American Mathematical Society, Providence

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman AJ (1963) The structure of fermion density matrices. Rev Mod Phys 35(3):668–87

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Da Costa N, Krause D (1994) Schrödinger logics. Stud Logica 53(4):533–550

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Da Costa N, Krause D (1999) Set theoretic models for quantum systems in language. Quantum, Music, Springer, pp 171–81

  • Dalla Chiara ML, Toralda Di Francia G (1985) Individuals, kinds and names in physics. Versus 40: 29–50, reprinted in Corsi, G. et al (eds) (1992) Bridging the gap: philosophy, mathematics and physics. Kluwer Acad Pub, Dordrecht, pp 261–283

  • Dalla Chiara ML, Toralda Di Francia G (1995) Identity questions from quantum theory. In: Gavroglu K, Stachel J, Wartofsky MW (eds) Physics, philosophy, and the scientific community. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 163. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Derksen H, Weyman J (2005) Quiver representations. Not Am Math Soc 52(2):200–6

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks D, Versteegh MAM (2008) Identical quantum particles and weak discernibility. Found Phys 38:923–34

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato M, Morganti M (2013) Grades of individuality. A pluralistic view of identity in quantum mechanics and the sciences. Philos Stud 163:591–610

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1978) Is logic empirical? (corrected from the original of 1976) in Truth and Other Enigmas. Duckworth, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Emch GG (1984) Mathematical and conceptual foundations of 20th-century physics. North Holland Mathematical Studies 100, North Holland

  • Finkelstein D (1963) The logic of quantum mechanics. Trans NY Acad Sci 25(6 Series II):621–637. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2164-0947.1963.tb01483.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein D (1981) Quantum sets, assemblies and Plexi. In: Beltrametti EG, van Fraassen BC (eds) Current issues in quantum logic. Plenum, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulis DJ, Randall CH (1979) Tensor products of quantum logics do not exist. Not Am Math Soc 26:557

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulis DJ, Randall CH (1981) Empirical logic and tensor products. In: Neumann H (ed) Interpretations and foundations of quantum theory. B. I. Wissenschaft, Mannheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Foulis DJ, Randall CH (1981) What are quantum logics and what ought they to be? In: Beltrametti EG, van Fraassen BC (eds) Current issues in quantum logic. Plenum, New York, pp 35–52

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • French S, Krause D (2006) Identity in physics: a historical, philosophical and formal analysis. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gelfand IM, Naimark MA (1943) On the embedding of normed linear rings into the ring of operators in Hilbert space. Mat Sbornik 12:197–213

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowers T (ed) (2009) The Princeton companion to mathematics. Princeton University Press, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffith AM (2015) Towards a pluralist theory of truthmaking. Erkenntnis 80(6):1157–1173

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Grillet PA (2001) Commutative semigroups. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote A (2003) Truthmakers and the alleged need for relevance. Logique et Analyse, 46, nos 183–4, September–December, pp 345–364

  • Heathcote A (2006) ‘Truthmaking and the gettier problem’ in aspects of knowing: epistemological essays, Ch. 10, ed. Stephen Hetherington, Amsterdam: Elsevier 2006, pp 51–67

  • Heathcote A (2012) Gettier and the stopped clock. Analysis 72(2):309–314. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/ans047

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote A (2014) Truthmaking, evidence of, and impossibility proofs. Acta Analytica. 29(3):363–75. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-013-0207-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote A (2018) Analyticity, truthmaking and mathematics Open. J Philos 8(2018):243–61. https://doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2018.83018

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote A (2020) Multiplicity and Indiscernibility. In: Synthese, 9th March 2020 on-line first . https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02600-8

  • Heathcote A (2021) Five indistinguishable spheres. Axiomathes 32:367–383. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-020-09531-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote A (2021) Countability and self-identity. Eur J Philos Sci 11:109. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-021-00423-z

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman G (1989) Mathematics without numbers. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan T (2001) Contextual semantics and metaphysical realism: truth as indirect correspondence. In: Lynch MP (ed) The nature of truth. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 67–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett N, Norton J (2013) Weak discernibility for quanta, the right way. Br J Philos Sci 65(1):39–58. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axs038

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Husimi K (1940) Some formal properties of the density matrix. Proc Phys Math Soc Jpn 1940(22):264–314

    Google Scholar 

  • Ischi B (2000) Endomorphisms of the separated product of lattices. Int J Theor Phys 39(11):2559–2581. https://doi.org/10.1023/a:1026405608135

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ischi B (2005) Orthocomplementation and compound systems. Int J Theor Phys 44(12):2207–2217. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10773-005-8016-0

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Jauch JM (1968) Foundations of quantum mechanics. Addison-Wesley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson N (2009) Basic algebra, vol 1, 2nd edn. Dover, Mineola NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Jago M (2009) The disjunction and conjunction theses. Mind 118(470):411–5

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Jordan P, von Neumann J, Wigner EP (1934) On an algebraic generalization of the quantum mechanical formalism. Ann Math 56:29–64

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1781) Critique of pure reason (trans. and Guyer P, Wood AW (ed), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Koslow A (1992) A structuralist theory of logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koslow A (2007) Structuralist logic: implications, inferences, and consequences. Log Univers 1(1):167–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-006-0008-1

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Koslow A (2019) The modality and non-extensionality of the quantifiers. Synthese 196:2545–2554. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0539-6

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Krause D (1992) On a quasi-set theory. Notre Dame J Form Log 33(3):402–11

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Krause D, Arenhart JRB (2018) Quantum non-individuality: background concepts and possibilities. In: The map and the Territory: exploring the foundations of science, thought and reality. Springer, New York

  • Krein M, Milman D (1940) On extreme points of regular convex sets. Stud Math 9(1):133–138

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis DK, Rosen G (2003) Postscript to things qua truthmakers: negative existentials. In: Lillehammer H, Rodriguez-Pereyra G (eds) Real Metaphysics (25–38). Routledge, London, pp 39–42

    Google Scholar 

  • de Sa López D (2009) Disjunctions, conjunctions, and their truthmakers. Mind 118(470):417–25

  • Martin CB (1996) How it is: entities, absences and voids. Australas J Philos 74(1):57–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin T (2005) The tale of quantum logic. In: Ben-Menahem Y (ed) Hilary Putnam. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 156–187. https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511614187.0

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McCrimmon K (2004) A taste of Jordan algebras. Universitext, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Mielnik B (2012) Convex Sets: a journey to the limits of our knowledge. arXiv:1202.2164v1 [quant-ph]

  • Molnar G (2000) Truthmakers for negative truths. Australas J Philos 78(1):72–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moody Ernest A (1953) Truth and Consequence in Mediaeval Logic. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, North-Holland, Amsterdam

  • Muller F (2015) The rise of relationals. Mind 124:201–237

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan K, Simons P, Smith B (1984) Truth-makers. Philos Phenomenol Res 44:287–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray FJ, von Neumann J (1936) On rings of operators. Ann Math (2) 31(1):116–229

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (2004) Tarski’s definition and truth-makers. Ann Pure Appl Logic 126:57–76

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Parker-Rhodes AF (1981) The theory of indistinguishables: a search for explanatory principles below the level of physics. D. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1885) On the algebra of logic: a contribution to the philosophy of notation. Am J Math 7:180–196

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Priest G (2000) Truth and contradiction. Philos Q 50(200):305–19

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Read S (2000) Truthmakers and the disjunction thesis. Mind 109(432):67–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rédei M (ed) (2005) John von Neumann: selected letters, history of mathematics, vol 27. American Mathematical Society, Providence

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra G (2006) Truthmaking, entailment, and the conjunction thesis. Mind 115(460):957–82

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra G (2009) The disjunction and conjunction theses. Mind 118(470):427–43

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1956) Logic and knowledge: essays 1901–1950. In: Marsh RC (ed) Allen and Unwin, London

  • Schaefer HH (1971) Topological vector spaces, graduate texts in mathematics 3. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer J (2010) The least discerning and most promiscuous truthmaker. Philos Q 60(239):307–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger K-G (1999) Toward quantum mathematics. I. From quantum set theory to universal quantum mechanics. J Math Phys 40(3):1344–1358. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.532806

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E (1936) Probability relations between separated systems. Math Proc Camb Philos Soc 32:446–452

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E (1950) What is an elementary particle? Endeavour 9:109–116. Reprinted in Castellani E (ed) Interpreting Bodies. Princeton University Press, Princeton 1998

  • Schneider R (1993) Convex bodies: the Brunn–Minkowski theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider C (1994) Probability: a new logico-semantical approach. J Gen Philos Sci 25(1):107–124. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00769280

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Segal IE (1947) Irreducible representations of operator algebras. Bull Am Math Soc 53:73–88

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Segal IE (1947) Postulates for general quantum mechanics. Ann Math (second series) 48(4):930–48

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sher G (2004) In search of a substantive theory of truth. J Philos 101(1):5–36

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Sher G (2013) Forms of correspondence: the intricate route from thought to reality. Pederson Wright 2013:157–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberg B (2016) Representation theory of finite monoids. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Takeuti G (1981) Quantum set theory. In: Beltrametti EG, van Fraassen BC (eds) Current issues in quantum logic. Plenum Press, New York, pp 303–322. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-3228-2_19

  • Takhtajan Leon A (2000) Quantum mechanics for mathematicians. Graduate Studies in Mathematics, vol 95, American Mathematical Society. Providence Rhode Island

  • Fraassen V, Bas C, Peschard I (2008) Identity over time: objectively. Subject Philos Q 58(230):15–35

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen BC (1991) Quantum mechanics; an empiricist view. Oxford, Clarendon Press.

  • Von Neumann J (1929) Zur Algebra der Funktionaloperationen und Theorie der normalen Operatoren. Math Ann 102:370–427

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J (1932) Mathematische grundlagen der quantenmechanik. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J (1936) On an algebraic generalisation of the quantum mechanical formalism (Part I). Mat Sborn I:415–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J (1947) The mathematician. In: Heywood RB (ed) Works of the mind. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright GH (1957) Logical studies. Routledge, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Waechter J (2017) Positive Truthmakers for Negative Truths: a solution to Molnar’s Problem. Philos Stud 174:579–92

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl H (1917) The continuum: a critical examination of the foundations of analysis. (reprinted in translation in Dover books 1987)

  • Weyl H (1931) The theory of groups and quantum mechanics (trans. of Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik, 2nd edn, Robertson HP (eds). Methuen, London (reprinted 1950 unaltered by Dover, N.Y.)

  • Wilce A (2010) Formalism and interpretation in quantum theory. Found Phys 40(4):434–462. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-010-9410-x

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Wilce A (2018) A royal road to quantum theory (or thereabouts). Entropy 20(4):227. https://doi.org/10.3390/e20040227

    Article  ADS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1921) Tractatus logico-philisophicus (Translated 1961 by Pears DF, McGuiness BF) Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

  • Wulfsohn A (1975) Tensor products of Jordan algebras. Can J Math 27(1):60–74

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank a reader of this journal for helpful remarks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Heathcote.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I declare there are no conflicts of interest or violations of ethical issues involved in this work.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Adrian Heathcote: Retired from University of Sydney.

Appendix on Monoids

Appendix on Monoids

A semigroup \((\mathscr {M}\,,\, \cdot )\) is a set of elements \(\mathscr {M}\,\) with an associative binary operation \(\cdot\). If the operation is commutative, so that

$$\begin{aligned} a \cdot b \;=\; b \cdot a \end{aligned}$$

then it is called a commutative semigroup. A semigroup that has an identity element  e  is a monoid \((\mathscr {M}\,,\, \cdot \; ,\; {\textit{e}})\), with, for all a,

$$\begin{aligned} e \cdot a \; = \; a \cdot e\; = \; a. \end{aligned}$$

This identity element is unique. It is a commutative monoid if the operation is commutative. An absorbing element  z  is an element such that, for all  a 

$$\begin{aligned} a \cdot z\; =\; z \cdot a\; = z. \end{aligned}$$

If an absorbing element exists then it is unique. An idempotent element is an element  u  such that

$$\begin{aligned} u \cdot u\; = \; u. \end{aligned}$$

Obviously the identity element is an idempotent element. A semilattice is a partially ordered set in which any pair of elements  a  and  b  have a meet, or greatest lower bound, \(a \wedge b\). Every semilattice is a commutative semigroup under the operation \(\, \wedge\). Commutative semigroups in which every element is an idempotent element are semilattices. If it is a monoid then it is a semilattice where the identity element is the least element.

A commutative semigroup, or monoid, is said to have the cancellative property when one has the following implication: for all elements of \(\mathscr {M}\,\)

$$\begin{aligned} \hbox {if}\;\; a \cdot b\; = \; a \cdot c\;\; \hbox {then}\;\; b\; =\; c . \end{aligned}$$

As an example, the non-negative integers under either addition or multiplication form a cancellative monoid. A cancellative semigroup can contain at most one idempotent element, namely the identity element.

There is a theorem that is attributed variously to Ore, Dubreil, or Grothendieck, to the effect that a commutative semigroup can be embedded in a group (in the sense that there is an isomorphic map into a subset of a group) if and only if it is cancellative. (For a non-commutative semigroup the conditions are more complex, but it is the commutative case that concerns us here.) In fact if a cancellative semigroup is finite then it is already a group. There is an explicit procedure for constructing the group completion of a monoid. For example, to construct the integers from the natural numbers \(\mathbb {N}\) one forms the negative integers by considering, for all  n , \(- {\textit{n}}\, := \, 0 - {\textit{n}}\). (See Grillet 2001, ch. 1), or Clifford and Preston (1964, ch. 1)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heathcote, A. The Problem of Truth in Quantum Mechanics. glob. Philosophy 33, 9 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-023-09656-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-023-09656-4

Keywords

Navigation