Skip to main content
Log in

Against ‘Interpretation’: Quantum Mechanics Beyond Syntax and Semantics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The question “what is an interpretation?” is often intertwined with the perhaps even harder question “what is a scientific theory?”. Given this proximity, we try to clarify the first question to acquire some ground for the latter. The quarrel between the syntactic and semantic conceptions of scientific theories occupied a large part of the scenario of the philosophy of science in the 20th century. For many authors, one of the two currents needed to be victorious. We endorse that such debate, at least in the terms commonly expressed, can be misleading. We argue that the traditional notion of “interpretation” within the syntax/semantic debate is not the same as that of the debate concerning the interpretation of quantum mechanics. As much as the term is the same, the term “interpretation” as employed in quantum mechanics has its meaning beyond (pure) logic. Our main focus here lies on the formal aspects of the solutions to the measurement problem. There are many versions of quantum theory, many of them incompatible with each other. In order to encompass a wider variety of approaches to quantum theory, we propose a different one with an emphasis on pure formalism. This perspective has the intent of elucidating the role of each so-called “interpretation” of quantum mechanics, as well as the precise origin of the need to interpret it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We will try to clear up confusion related to the terms “language” and “meaning”. Terms are the linguistic representations for certain quantities—for example, the term “mass” designates the physical quantity known as mass. Measuring, thus, is related to quantities, not their linguistic representations. In this sense, terms, of course, cannot be measured.

  2. Probably the first author to point out this problem was Maxwell (1962).

  3. It’s not our point here to discuss, in a profound way, how the traditional distinction can be if necessary, safeguarded [a more detailed discussion can be found at Silva (2013, pp. 144–151)]. D Lewis (1970) and Maxwell (1962) suggested how this can be done from a realist perspective and the recent developments in the structural realist view of theories depend/draw heavily on an adequate distinction between observational and theoretical terms.

  4. From this point forward, we will adopt the notation presented by Krause and Arenhart (2016), who call first-order structures as “order-1”, and high-order structures (e.g., with \(n>1\)) as “order-n”.

  5. Something that, again, Carnap was aware (cf. Carnap 1966, p. 193)

  6. (cf. Carnap 1959, p. 158) and Carnap (1966, p. 228).

  7. In this sense, Carnap is in partial disagreement with Quine’s holism: i.e., recognizing the continuum between theoretical and observational terms—and so only partially agreeing with Quine’s holism—but allowing a distinction to be justified (only) by practical purposes, suspending the judgment about its “nature”, that he would regard as a (suspicious) metaphysical commitment.

  8. For a detailed discussion see Silva (2020, pp. 87–95).

  9. It is noteworthy to mention that the terminology of “partial interpretation” is employed here in a non-standard way. It shall not to confused with its standard meaning: if every elementary statement in a theory T has a correspondent in its models, then it is considered to be a “full interpretation”; otherwise, it is a “partial interpretation” (cf. Haskell (1963, p. 48).

  10. We’ll say more about this in Sect. 4.

  11. It is not our goal to discuss the implications of this view for scientific realism; the reader interested in this subject may find a helpful discussion in Chakravartty (2001) and references therein.

  12. Although Chang and Keisler (1990) work only with order-1 structures, the idea can be generalized.

  13. This is also the case for non-standard semantics, such as Henkin semantics, see Henkin (1950) and Enderton (2015, Sect. 3). Nevertheless, we will stick with the standard case.

  14. For simplicity, from this point forward the description of these structures’ components shall be fixed as defined in the previous paragraph.

  15. See also Lutz (2015, Sect. 5).

  16. This issue is discussed in more detail in Sect. 6.

  17. Another way of stating such problem is relating “open” and “closed” systems—see Pessoa Junior (1997). This work, however, sticks to Maudlin’s taxonomy as it better relates to the literature here considered.

  18. In the sense of the word ‘interpretation’, as usually employed in QM.

  19. In his “Against ‘measurement”’, Bell (1990) put forth his famous critique of how the notion of “measurement” is ill-defined and even inadequate to the context of the foundations of QM. Our goal here is essentially to do the same, but with the term “interpretation”.

  20. For a critical summary of various formulations of QM, see Wightman (1976), Gudder (1979), Styer et al. (2002), and references therein.

  21. For those cases, see the references cited in Ćirković (2005, p. 821).

  22. For a brief analysis of seven thought experiments that show the differences in experimental results between collapse and no-collapse approaches versions of QM, see Ćirković (2005, pp. 823–834).

  23. An earlier version of \(\hbox {QM}^{bas}\) was presented in Arroyo (2020, Chap. 2).

  24. It is assumed, though, that this can be done—even if not here.

  25. See \({\mathcal {R}}\) ahead.

  26. Not to be confused with the “cosmic exile” mentioned in Sect. 4.

  27. There is some consensus concerning this mode of presentation of measurement results. For the sake of precision, it is essential to emphasize that this applies to measurements of the first kind. There are, however, measurements where this does not occur: where the eigenstate does not correspond to the eigenvalue. The position measurement satisfies the postulate presented, but, strictly, this does not apply to the measurement of energy.

  28. Recall that such a specific axiom is neutral regarding the question whether the states or the systems are prone to the branching process.

  29. Basically, this is the lead done by Niels Bohr (cf. Faye 2012, and references therein).

References

  • Achinstein P (1968) Concepts of science: a philosophical analysis. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Acuña P (2021) Charting the landscape of interpretation, theory rivalry, and underdetermination in quantum mechanics. Synthese 198(2):1711–1740

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arroyo RW (2020) Discussions on physics, metaphysics and metametaphysics: Interpreting quantum mechanics. PhD thesis, Federal University of Santa Catarina (UFSC), Florianópolis. https://tede.ufsc.br/teses/PFIL0381-T.pdf. Accessed 29 Jun 2021

  • Arroyo RW, Arenhart JRB (2019) Between physics and metaphysics: a discussion of the status of mind in quantum mechanics. In: de Barros JA, Montemayor C (eds) Quanta and mind: essays on the connection between quantum mechanics and the consciousness, synthese library. Springer, Cham, Chap 3, pp 31–42

  • Auyang SY (1995) How is quantum field theory possible?. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell J (1990) Against ‘measurement’. Phys World 3(8):33–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff G, von Neumann J (1936) The logic of quantum mechanics. Ann Math 37(4):823–843

  • Bohm D (1952) A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of ‘hidden’ variables, i. Phys Rev 85(2):166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm D, Hiley BJ (2006) The undivided universe: an ontological interpretation of quantum theory. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno O, Krause D (2007) Scientific theories, models, and the semantic approach. Principia 11(2):187–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1959) Theoretical concepts in science. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part A 31(1):158–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1966) Philosophical foundations of physics: an introduction to the philosophy of science. Basic Books, Editor Martin Gardner

  • Chakravartty A (2001) The semantic or model-theoretic view of theories and scientific realism. Synthese 127:325–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang CC, Keisler HJ (1990) Model theory, vol 3. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Ćirković MM (2005) Physics versus semantics: a puzzling case of the missing quantum theory. Found Phys 35(5):817–838

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen-Tannoudji C, Diu B, Laloe F (1991) Quantum mechanics, vol 1. Wiley, Weinheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa G (2006) Scientific models, partial structures and the new received view of theories. Stud Hist Philos Sci 2(37):370–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2008) Structures of scientific theories. In: Machamer P, Silbertstein M (eds) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Wiley, Oxford, pp 55–79

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • da Costa NCA, Chuaqui R (1988) On Suppes’ set theoretical predicates. Erkenntnis 29(1):95–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • da Costa NCA, French S (2000) Models, theories, and structures: thirty years on. Philos Sci 67:S116–S127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalla Chiara ML (1977) Logical self reference, set theoretical paradoxes and the measurement problem in quantum mechanics. J Philos Log 6(1):331–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dalla Chiara ML (1981) Logical foundations of quantum mechanics. In: Agazzi E (ed) Modern logic—a survey: historical. In: Philosophical and mathematical aspects of modern logic and its applications. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 331–351

  • Dalla Chiara ML, di Francia TG (1979) Formal analysis of physical theories. In: di Francia TG (ed) Problems in the foundations of physics. Worldcat, Amsterdam, pp 134–201

    Google Scholar 

  • de Barros JA, Oas G (2017) Can we falsify the consciousness-causes-collapse hypothesis in quantum mechanics? Found Phys 47(10):1294–1308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Ronde C (2016) Representational realism, closed theories and the quantum to classical limit. World Scientific, Singapore, pp 105–135

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Espagnat B (2003) Veiled reality: an analysis of present-day quantum mechanical concepts. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Dürr D, Lazarovici D (2020) Understanding quantum mechanics: the world according to modern quantum foundations. Springer, Cham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Enderton HB (2015) Second-order and higher-order logic. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, fall 2015 edn. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford

  • Esfeld M (2019) Individuality and the account of nonlocality: the case for the particle ontology in quantum physics. In: Lombardi O, Fortin S, López C, Holik F (eds) Quantum worlds: perspectives on the ontology of quantum mechanics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 222–244

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Everett H (1957) ‘Relative state’ formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev Mod Phys 29(3):454–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farenick D (2016) Fundamentals of functional analysis, 1st edn. Universitext, Springer, Switzerland

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faye J (2012) Niels Bohr: his heritage and legacy: an anti-realist view of quantum mechanics, vol 6. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Friederich S (2014) Interpreting quantum theory: a therapeutic approach. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardi GC, Rimini A, Weber T (1986) Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys Rev D 34(2):470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein S (2009) Projection postulate. In: Greenberger D, Hentschel K, Weinert F (eds) Compendium of quantum physics: concepts, experiments, history and philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 499–501

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gudder SP (1979) A survey of axiomatic quantum mechanics. In: Hooker C (ed) The logico-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics, Contemporary consolidation, vol II. Springer, Netherlands, pp 323–363

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson H (2012) What scientific theories could not be. Philos Sci 79(2):183–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson H (2016) Scientific theories. In: Humphreys P (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science. Oxford University Press, Oxford Chap 27

    Google Scholar 

  • Haskell CB (1963) Foundations of mathematical logic. McCraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkin L (1950) Completeness in the theory of types. J Symb Log 15(02):81–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodges W (1993) Model theory, Encyclopedia of mathematics and its applications, vol 42. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer M (1974) The philosophy of quantum mechanics: the interpretations of quantum mechanics in historical perspective. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause D, Arenhart JRB (2016) The logical foundations of scientific theories: languages, structures, and models. Routledge, Abingdon

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Krause D, Arenhart JRB, Moraes FTF (2011) Axiomatization and models of scientific theories. Found Sci 16(4):363–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1970) How to define theoretical terms. J Philos 67(13):427

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis P (2016) Quantum ontology: a guide to the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz S (2012) On a straw man in the philosophy of science: a defense of the received view. HOPOS: J Int Soc Hist Philos Sci 2(1):77–120

  • Lutz S (2015) What was the syntax-semantics debate in the philosophy of science about? Philos Phenomenol Res 95(2):319–352.

  • Maudlin T (1995) Three measurement problems. Topoi 14(1):7–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell G (1962) The ontological status of theoretical entities. Minn Stud Philos Sci 3:1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Mermin ND (2004) Could Feynman have said this? Phys Today 57(5):10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messiah A (1961) Quantum mechanics, vol I. North-Holland, Amsterdam translated by G. M. Temmer

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller FA (2003) Refutability revamped: how quantum mechanics saves the phenomena. Erkenntnis 56:189–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ney A, Albert DZ (eds) (2013) The wave function: essays on the metaphysics of quantum mechanics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pessoa OF Jr (1997) Can the decoherence approach help to solve the measurement problem? Synthese 113(3):323–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1966) What theories are not. Stud Log Found Math 44:240–251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche L (2018) Getting real about quantum mechanics. In: Saatsi J (ed) The Routledge handbook of scientific realism. Routledge, New York, pp 291–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Silva GOd (2013) Carnap and Kuhn on linguistic frameworks and scientific revolutions. Manuscrito 36(1):139–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silva GOd (2020) Os empiristas vão à missa: compromissos ontológicos e frameworks linguísticos. PhD thesis, University of Campinas (UNICAMP), Campinas. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/342469. Accessed 29 Jun 2021

  • Sklar L (2003) Interpreting theories: the case of statistical mechanics. In: Clark P, Hawley K (eds) Philosophy of science today. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 276–284

    Google Scholar 

  • Styer DF, Balkin MS, Becker KM, Burns MR, Dudley CE, Forth ST, Gaumer JS, Kramer MA, Oertel DC, Park LH, Rinkoski MT, Smith CT, Wotherspoon TD (2002) Nine formulations of quantum mechanics. Am J Phys 70(3):288–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1977) The structure of scientific theories. University of Illinois Press, Illinois

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1989) The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. University of Illinois Press, Illinois

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (2000) Understanding scientific theories: an assessment of developments, 1969–1998. Philos Sci 67:S102–S115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1957) Introduction to logic. Van Nostrand, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1967) What is a scientific theory? In: Morgenbesser S (ed) Philosophy of science today. Basic Books, New York, pp 55–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (2002) Representation and invariance of scientific structures. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski A (1956) The concept of truth in formalized languages. Log, Semant, Metamath 2:152–278

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen BC (1989) Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press, Oxford, Clarendon paperbacks

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J (1955) Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace D (2012) The emergent multiverse: quantum theory according to the Everett interpretation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace D (2020a) Lessons from realistic physics for the metaphysics of quantum theory. Synthese 197(10):4303–4318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace D (2020b) On the plurality of quantum theories: quantum theory as a framework, and its implications for the quantum measurement problem. Sci Real Quant 5:78–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Wightman AS (1976) Hilbert’s sixth problem: mathematical treatment of the axioms of physics. In: Browder FE (ed) Mathematical developments arising from Hilbert problems, part 1, Proceedings of symposia in pure mathematics, vol XXVIII. American Mathematical Society, Rhode Island, pp 241–268

  • Wigner E (1983) Remarks on the mind-body question. In: Wheeler J, Zurek W (eds) Quantum theory and measurement. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 168–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall J (2007) Miracles and models: why reports of the death of structural realism may be exaggerated. R Inst Philos Suppl 61:125–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahar EG (2004) Ramseyfication and structural realism. Theoria 19(1):5–30

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We want to thank all the attendants of the VI International Workshop on Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Information: Identity and Individuality, held in Florianópolis, Brazil, 2019, in which part of the content of this paper was presented. In special, we also thank Adonai Sant’Anna, Christian de Ronde, David Wallace, Décio Krause, Eduardo Quirino, Jerzy Brzozowski, Jonas Arenhart, Kherian Gracher, Lauro Nunes Filho, Matheus Valente, Osvaldo Pessoa Jr., and Otávio Bueno for many fruitful discussions on related subjects, and for comments made on previous versions of this paper. We would also like to thank the anonymous reviewer for having raised several questions that allowed us to improve our article. Part of the content of this paper was also presented in chapters 1 and 2 of one of the authors’ doctoral thesis (RWA), which was financed in part by the Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior—Brasil (CAPES)—Finance Code 001.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raoni Wohnrath Arroyo.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arroyo, R.W., da Silva, G.O. Against ‘Interpretation’: Quantum Mechanics Beyond Syntax and Semantics. Axiomathes 32, 1243–1279 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09579-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09579-y

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Physics and Astronomy Classification Scheme

Navigation