Skip to main content
Log in

Model Organisms as Simulators: The Context of Cross-Species Research and Emergence

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Model organisms are a living form of scientific models. Despite the widespread use of model organisms in scientific research, the actual representational relationship between model organisms and their target species is often poorly characterized in the context of cross-species research. Many model organisms do not represent the target species adequately, let alone accurately. This is partly due to the complex and emergent life phenomena in the organism, and partly due to the fact that a model organism is always taken to represent a broad range of diverse organisms. More often than not, model organisms are taken as a reference point for an extrapolation to be made to the unknown characteristics of other species. I propose to view model organisms as analogue simulators which represent the emergent phenomenon in the context of cross-species research. A model organism represents a wide range of species by simulating their molecular microstates which underlie various emergent phenomena. I show that although model organisms represent the target species inadequately at many levels of complexity, they have epistemic values as a simulator in virtue of which the emergent phenomenon can be modeled dynamically, a virtue that is hardly attainable by non-dynamic models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Organisms with highly similar genes might differ in various cellular and molecular characteristics, such as mutation rate, synonymous codon usage, protein expression profiles, RNA regulations, and epigenetics.

  2. Mark Davis warns that although humanized mouse modeling is promising, ‘it should not be assumed that such mice are equivalent to a human immune system in any respect unless it is demonstrated to be so by a variety of objective measures.’ (2008, p. 836).

  3. Biologists are aware of this dilemma of representation. They recognize that the success of a model organism (and an animal model) representation is domain-relative. Lampson (2013) suggests to use an animal model to answer specific questions rather than broad questions in order to make the model more successful. Cheon and Orsulic (2011) claim that an ideal mouse model of human cancer needs to fulfill a list of stringent criteria in various domains, some of which are drug response, chemoresistance, and histopathology.

  4. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing me to Rosen’s works. Rosen’s mathematical works in theoretical biology have been embraced and clarified by his student Louie (2014).

  5. It is a common understanding among philosophers of biology to take model organisms as a type of living model rather than a type of simulator. I surmise that one of the main reasons is that model organisms share many characteristics of the models. Another reason could be that the term ‘simulator’ has always been associated with ‘computer simulation’, despite the fact that it can be used to refer to analogue simulators such as a wind tunnel. In the literature, model organisms are always regarded as a material model (see Meunier 2012; Huber and Keuck 2013).

  6. In this paper, I can only provide a cursory explanation of these four reasons. A detailed defense of them requires a separate paper. My aim in this paper is to focus on the representation of the emergent phenomenon in the context of cross-species research.

  7. Though Morrison is speaking in the context of computer simulations, it is applicable in the context of analogue simulations.

  8. There is no reason to claim that only a computer simulation is dynamic but an analogue simulation is not. Engineers and scientists do recognize the dynamic nature of analogue simulations, such as a physical wind tunnel simulation. See Ahmad et al. (2005).

  9. See Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2010) for a philosophical analysis.

  10. In an animal model of clinical research, specific diseases and pathological conditions can be simulated via adroitly implemented procedures. For example, aortic stenosis in many species could be simulated using supracoronary banding of the aorta of an animal model (Gross 2009, p. 207; Yarbrough et al. 2012). This type of procedural simulation involves relatively large equipments as compared to the molecular and cellular approach.

  11. According to Winsberg’s definition of a simulation, what qualifies something as a simulation can be the fact that the object in question is actually functioning as a simulator (e.g., a computer simulation of the big bang), or that the object in question is hoped or believed to function as a simulator. He writes, “Any object that we study because we think or hope it is dynamically similar enough for us to learn about basins of fluid by studying it is a simulation of a basin of fluid.” (2009, p. 836; my emphasis).

  12. My view is similar to Rosen’s idea that the basis for system analogy which underlies modeling is the common function of two systems under comparison (Rosen 2000, p. 280).

  13. Not to discount the fact that model organisms are similar to some target species, despite they are not (but hoped to) similar to a wide gamut of others.

  14. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out that a simulator needs to be a model of the target system to warrant the structural congruence between both systems.

  15. Dardashti et al. (2017) enumerate a list of prospective cases of analogue simulations in physics. I do not embrace their conditions for an analogue simulation because their account requires mathematical accuracy and syntactic isomorphism between the simulator and the target system, which is inappropriate for the case of model organisms as a simulation of target species.

  16. Although Paul Humphreys’s paper argues for computer simulations, it is applicable to analogue simulations as well.

  17. I contend that the scientific insight provided by model organisms is more important than the exact result that can be extrapolated to the target species. Like a climate simulation model, the significance of model organisms as a simulator lies in the insights learned from the experimentation rather than in the practical solution provided.

  18. Though the finding garnered from model organism studies may not be generalizable to all respects of life phenomena and to all species, it is still critical in providing useful insights into many domains. Besides, it is not always necessary to specifically experiment on a particular organism to learn about it when such insight can be obtained reliably from model organism studies.

  19. This is evidenced in an investigation of the regulation of DNA replication timing during mammalian development. The researchers used a mouse model to simulate the replication mechanism in mammals. The similarity between the mouse model and other species, which is a characteristic feature of simulation, is revealed in the following paragraphs: “Furthermore, changes in replication time are linked to changes in sub-nuclear organization and domain-wide transcriptional potential, and tissue-specific replication timing profiles are conserved from mouse to human, suggesting that the program has developmental significance. Hence, these studies have provided a solid foundation for linking megabase level chromosome structure to function […]” (Pope et al. 2010, p. 127; my emphasis).

  20. It is analogous to the view that although two physical objects (say, water and ice) consist of the same material (i.e., atoms), they may possess different chemical properties due to the different configuration of the atoms, therefore renders them ontologically distinct at the chemical level. This is similar to my claim that a model organism and its target species are distinct ontologically at the emergent level, for the same molecular and cellular components in both organisms have different configurations when giving rise to phenotypes. After all, all objects are made up of the same material—atoms. It is the configuration of the material that matters.

  21. For example, Weber (1999) holds that simulations can be employed to explore the putative routes of emergence of the immune system.

  22. Simulation studies in protein folding are indispensable because experimental studies are unpromising in virtue of the low-resolution structural data yielded with sufficient temporal resolution (Freddolino et al. 2010). In addition, it was reported that physical models of protein folding are lagging behind simulations and bioinformatics approaches (Dill et al. 2007). In characterizing the emergent nature of protein folding, Thirumalai et al. (2010) conclude that both theoretical framework and simulations (which employ a variety of coarse-grained models) are significant in making testable predictions for protein folding.

  23. Johannes Lenhard (2007) argues that simulation takes a form of exploratory cooperation between experimentation and theoretical modeling, in the sense that simulation models are determined by the data and dependent on the right fundamental equations of theoretical models. Simulation is set to run through a process of iterative reciprocal comparison between experiment and model.

  24. Bedau argues against the traditionally stronger notion of emergence according to which a strong form of downward causation is involved. He maintains that this type of emergence is irrelevant in science (Bedau 1997).

  25. Model organisms are artificially constructed in the laboratory through various genetic and molecular manipulations. In terms of the artificiality of model organisms, emergent phenomena observed in model organisms are comparable to Bedau’s view that simulations “produce artificial examples of weak emergence” (Bedau 2012, p. 91).

  26. It is not uncommon that philosophers treat organisms as machines. See Nicholson (2014) and Holm & Powell (2013).

References

  • Abundo M, Accardi L, Rosato N, Stella L (2002) Analysing protein energy data by a stochastic model for cooperative interactive interactions: comparison and characterization of cooperativity. J Math Biol 44:341–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahmad K, Khare M, Chaudhry KK (2005) Wind tunnel simulation studies on dispersion at urban street canyons and intersections—a review. J Wind Eng Ind Aerodyn 93:697–717

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny RA (2000) Fashioning descriptive models in biology: of worms and wiring diagrams. Philos Sci 67:S260–S272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny RA (2001) Model organisms as models: understanding the ‘Lingua Franca’ of the Human Genome Project. Philos Sci 68(3):S251–S261

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny RA, Leonelli S (2011) What’s so special about model organisms? Stud Hist Philos Sci 42:313–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (2010) Dynamic mechanistic explanation: computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Stud Hist Philos Sci 41:321–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau MA (1997) Weak emergence. Noûs. 31(Suppl. 11):375–399

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau MA (2012) Weak emergence and computer simulation. In: Humphreys P, Imbert C (eds) Models, simulations, and representations. Routledge, New York, pp 91–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau MA, Humphreys P (2008) Introduction to philosophical perspectives on emergence. In: Bedau MA, Humphreys P (eds) Emergence: contemporary readings in philosophy and science. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 9–18

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bilen J, Bonini NM (2005) Drosophila as a model for human neurodegenerative disease. Annu Rev Genet 39:153–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolker J (1995) Model systems in developmental biology. BioEssays 17(5):451–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno O (2014) Computer simulation: an inferential conception. Monist 97(3):378–398

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (1997) Exploratory experimentation and the role of histochemical techniques in the work of Jean Brachet, 1938–1952. Hist Philos Life Sci 19:27–45

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian RM (2007) On microRNA and the need for exploratory experimentation in post-genomic molecular biology. Hist Philos Life Sci 29(3):285–311

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheon D-J, Orsulic S (2011) Mouse models of cancer. Annu Rev Pathol 6:95–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobrinik D (2013) Learning about retinoblastoma from mouse models that missed. In: Martínez-Murillo R, Martínez A (eds) Animal models of brain tumors. Springer, New York, pp 141–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Dardashti R, Thébault K, Winsberg E (2017) Confirmation via analogue simulation: what dumb holes could tell us about gravity. Br J Philos Sci 68(1):55–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis M (2008) A prescription for human immunology. Immunity 29:835–838

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dill KA, Ozkan SB, Weikl TR, Chodera JD, Voelz VA (2007) The protein folding problem: when will it be solved? Curr Opin Struct Biol 17:342–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott KC (2007) Varieties of exploratory experimentation in nanotoxicology. Hist Philos Life Sci 29(3):313–336

    Google Scholar 

  • Enciso M, Rey A (2011) Improvement of structure-based potentials for protein folding by native and nonnative hydrogen bonds. Biophys J 101:1474–1482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans C, Hartenstein V, Banerjee U (2003) Thicker than blood: conserved mechanisms in Drosophila and vertebrate hematopoiesis. Dev Cell 5:673–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fersht AR (2008) From the first protein structures to our current knowledge of protein folding: delights and scepticisms. Nat Rev Mol Cell Biol 9:650–654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin LR (2005) Exploratory experiments. Philos Sci 72(5):888–899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freddolino PL, Harrison CB, Liu Y, Schulten K (2010) Challenges in protein-folding simulations. Nat Phys 6:751–758

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasch AP, Payseur BA, Pool JE (2016) The power of natural variation for model organism biology. Trends Genet 32(3):147–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross DR (2009) Animal models in cardiovascular research. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guala F (2002) Models, simulations, and experiments. In: Magnani L, Nersessian N (eds) Model-based reasoning: science, technology, values. Springer, New York, pp 59–74

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heljasvaara R, Pihlajaniemi T (2011) Experimental tumour models in mice. In: Brakebusch C, Pihlajaniemi T (eds) Mouse as a model organism: from animals to cells. Springer, Berlin, pp 89–104

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Holm S, Powell R (2013) Organism, machine, artifact: the conceptual and normative challenges of synthetic biology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 44:627–631

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber L, Keuck LK (2013) Mutant mice: experimental organisms as materialised models in biomedicine. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 44:385–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys P (1991) Computer simulations. In: PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, vol 2, pp 497–506

  • Humphreys P (1997) Emergence, not supervenience. Philos Sci 64:S337–S345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iijima K, Liu H-P, Chiang A-S, Hearn SA, Konsolaki M, Zhong Y (2004) Dissecting the pathological effects of human Aβ40 and Aβ42 in Drosophila: a potential model for Alzheimer’s disease. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 101(17):6623–6628

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikami K, Nuzhat N, Lei L (2017) Organelle transport during mouse oocyte differentiation in germline cysts. Curr Opin Cell Biol 44:14–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson BR (2010) Eliminating the mystery from the concept of emergence. Biol Philos 25:843–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lampson LA (2013) Brain tumor models to predict clinical outcome: like the phoenix? In: Martínez-Murillo R, Martínez A (eds) Animal models of brain tumors. Humana Press, Clifton, pp 3–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard J (2007) Computer simulation: the cooperation between experimenting and modeling. Philos Sci 74(2):176–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S, Ankeny RA (2012) Re-thinking organisms: the impact of databases on model organism biology. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:29–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louie A (2014) More than life itself: a synthetic continuation in relational biology. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Mak I, Evaniew N, Ghert M (2014) Lost in translation: animal models and clinical trials in cancer treatment. Am J Transl Res 6(2):114–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought: diversity, evolution, and inheritance. The Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Meunier R (2012) Stages in the development of a model organism as a platform for mechanistic models in developmental biology: Zebrafish, 1970–2000. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 43:522–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell SD (2003) Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS (2005) Experiments versus models: new phenomena, inference and surprise. J Econ Methodol 12(2):317–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison M (2009) Models, measurement and computer simulation: the changing face of experimentation. Philos Stud 143:33–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian N, MacLeod M (2017) Models and simulations. In: Magnani L, Bertolotti T (eds) Springer handbook of model-based science. Springer, Berlin, pp 119–132

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson DJ (2014) The machine conception of the organism in development and evolution: a critical analysis. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 48:162–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pope B, Hiratani I, Gilbert D (2010) Domain-wide regulation of DNA replication timing during mammalian development. Chromosome Res 18(1):127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pradel E, Ewbank J (2004) Genetic models in pathogenesis. Ann Rev Genet 38:347–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratti E (2015) Big data biology: between eliminative inferences and exploratory experiments. Philos Sci 82(2):198–218

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid R (2007) Biological emergences: evolution by natural experiment. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1991) Life itself: a comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (2000) Essays on Life Itself. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sivakumar W, Couldwell W (2013) Pituitary models. In: Martínez-Murillo R, Martínez A (eds) Animal models of brain tumors. Springer, New York, pp 175–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinle F (1997) Entering new fields: exploratory uses of experimentation. Philos Sci 64:S65–S74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thirumalai D, O’Brien E, Morrison G, Hyeon C (2010) Theoretical perspectives on protein folding. Ann Rev Biophys 39:159–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulmschneider M, Ulmschneider J (2010) Implicit membrane models for peptide folding and insertion studies. In: Sansom M, Biggin P (eds) Molecular simulations and biomembranes: from biophysics to function. RSC Publishing, Cambridge, pp 91–145

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Gunsteren W, Dolenc J, Mark AE (2008) Molecular simulation as an aid to experimentalists. Curr Opin Struct Biol 18:149–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber BH (1999) Irreducible complexity and the problem of biochemical emergence. Biol Philos 14:593–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White RM (2015) Cross-species oncogenomics using zebrafish models of cancer. Curr Opin Genet Dev 30:73–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wightman B, Ha I, Ruvkun G (1993) Posttranscriptional regulation of the heterochronic gene lin-14 by lin-4 mediates temporal pattern formation in C. elegans. Cell 75:855–862

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt W (2000) Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of reductionisms. Found Sci 5(3):269–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg E (2009) Computer simulation and the philosophy of science. Philos Compass 4(5):835–845

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg E (2010) Science in the age of computer simulation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yarbrough WM, Mukherjee R, Ikonomidis JS, Zile MR, Spinale FG (2012) Myocardial remodeling with aortic stenosis and after aortic valve replacement: mechanisms and future prognostic implications. J Thorac Cardiovasc Surg 143(3):656–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sim-Hui Tee.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tee, SH. Model Organisms as Simulators: The Context of Cross-Species Research and Emergence. Axiomathes 29, 363–382 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09415-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-019-09415-4

Keywords

Navigation