Skip to main content

Why Indefinites?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Redefining Indefinites

Part of the book series: Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory ((SNLT,volume 85))

Abstract

The chapter contains a brief overview of the main arguments in favor of the hypothesis that indefinite DPs are neither referential nor quantificational expressions, but rather a third type of DP. We then present the various analyses that can be found in the formal semantics literature over the past 30 years, which treat indefinite DPs as free variables, choice functions, Skolem terms or properties. We then attempt to define the main semantic properties of indefinite DPs and finally we present the interpretation problems raised by this class of DPs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We will not differentiate between the terms quantified and quantificational.

  2. 2.

    It is currently assumed that DPs associated with the copular verb be function as predicates. This issue will be examined in detail in Chap. 2.

  3. 3.

    sm is the weak (i.e., unaccented) form of some.

  4. 4.

    Most semantic models assume at least one additional rule, predicate modification. But it is primarily for reasons of simplicity of exposition that this choice is made, since technically, one can limit oneself to functional application (cf. Heim and Kratzer 1998: 61ff).

  5. 5.

    The domain of truth values, notated Dt, is composed of two elements, true and false, notated 1 and 0 respectively.

  6. 6.

    The formal representation of cardinals (see (8c′)) requires first-order logic with identity.

  7. 7.

    If the same sentence contains more than one quantified DP, their relative scope may vary (see Chap. 6).

  8. 8.

    This mapping may be affected by contrastive stress.

  9. 9.

    The need for such a rule is generally assumed in models of the syntax-semantics interface: see Montague’s rule of “Quantifying in” or May’s (1985) “Quantifier Raising”. However, it is not clear whether this rule obeys general constraints on syntactic movement, as claimed by May (1985). Cf. Chap. 6.

  10. 10.

    A detailed analysis of donkey sentences will be provided in Chap. 8.

  11. 11.

    In Kamp’s discourse representation structures, an indefinite DP contributes a discourse referent and a condition on that discourse referent. Although technically different, free variables and discourse referents are comparable at the stage of evaluation.

  12. 12.

    According to Reinhart, a subset of indefinite DPs does not behave like generalized quantifiers and should be represented by means of choice functions. Winter, on the other hand, maintains that all indefinites should be represented by choice functions.

  13. 13.

    In the literature, this point is known as the empty restriction problem or the Donald Duck problem.

  14. 14.

    Steedman insists that Skolem terms do not denote functions (a constant Skolem function is merely part of their representation) but are referential terms (type e) that are assigned structured representations.

  15. 15.

    According to Steedman (2006) the scope of indefinites is always assigned in situ and depends on ‘generalized Skolem term specification’, which is an “anytime” operation, in the sense that it can apply at any point in a derivation: a Skolem term is specified as a constant if the specification operation applies as soon as the DP constituent has been formed, i.e., before the DP combines with, e.g., some quantified expression; it is specified as a dependent Skolem term if the specification operation applies only after the indefinite DP combines with the main predicate and other arguments of that predicate.

  16. 16.

    An alternative solution is to say that many takes a third argument, one that corresponds to the norm. This argument must be contextually instantiated. Once the norm is determined, many becomes conservative.

  17. 17.

    Formally, a determiner Det is said to be extensional if and only if for all A, B, E and E′ such that E′  Ê  E and Det A B is true in E, then Det A B is also true in E′.

  18. 18.

    Here, we are not taking presuppositions into account.

  19. 19.

    This point is still under debate. Thus, Keenan (1996) notes that, unlike other proportional determiners, every is not necessarily defined as a relation between the cardinality of (AÇB) and the cardinality of A. Knowing the cardinality of A is not necessary to verify that Every A is B, since it is enough to check whether the set of A’s that do not verify B is empty.

References

  • Abusch, D. 1994. The scope of indefinites. Natural Language Semantics 2: 83–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attal, P. 1976. A propos de l’indéfini des: Problèmes de représentation sémantique. Le français moderne 44(2): 126–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., and R. Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 4(2): 159–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beghelli, F., and T. Stowell. 1997. Distributivity and negation: The syntax of each and every. In Ways of scope taking, ed. A. Szabolcsi, 71–107. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, G.N. 1977a. A unified analysis of the English bare plural. Linguistics and Philosophy 1: 413–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, S., and W. Ladusaw. 2003. Restriction and saturation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diesing, M. 1992. Indefinites. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobrovie-Sorin, C. 1997a. Types of predicates and the representation of existential readings. In Proceedings of SALT VII, ed. A. Lawson, 117–134. Ithaca/New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobrovie-Sorin, C. 1997b. Classes de prédicats, distribution des indéfinis et la distinction thétique-catégorique. Le Gré des Langues 12: 58–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobrovie-Sorin, C., and C. Beyssade. 2004. Définir les indéfinis. Paris: Editions du CNRS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. 1981. Quantifier scope and syntactic islands. In Proceedings of the Chicago linguistic society, vol. 7, 59–66. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. 1997a. Dependent Indefinites. In Empirical issues in formal syntax and semantics, ed. F. Corblin, D. Godard, and J.-M. Marandin, 243–268. Berne: Peter Lang Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. 1997b. Evaluation indices and scope. In Ways of scope taking, ed. A. Szabolcsi, 183–215. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. 2001. Dependent indefinites and direct scope. In Logical perspectives on language and information, ed. C. Condoravdi and G. Renardel, 41–72. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D., and Y. Sugioka. 1983. Restrictive if/when clauses. Linguistics and Philosophy 6(2): 225–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.D., and I.A. Sag. 1982. Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 5: 355–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gamut, L.T.F. 1991. Logic, language and meaning. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon, B.S. 1996. Collectivity and distributivity internal to English noun phrases. Language Sciences 18(1–2): 443–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. 1982. The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst. Published in 1988, Garland, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., and A. Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. 1981. A theory of truth and discourse representation. In Formal methods in the study of language, ed. J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, and M. Stokhof, 277–322. Amsterdam: Mathematisch Centrum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, E.L. 1987. A semantic definition of indefinite NP. In The representation of (in)definiteness, ed. E. Reuland and A. ter Meulen, 287–317. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, E.L. 1996. The semantics of determiners. In The handbook of contemporary semantic theory, ed. S. Lappin, 42–63. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, E.L., and J. Stavi. 1986. A semantic characterization of natural language determiners. Linguistics and Philosophy 9: 253–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 1988. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In ed. Krifka, 247–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. 1995. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In The generic book, ed. G.N. Carlson and F.J. Pelletier, 125–175. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladusaw, W. 1994. Thetic and categorical, stage and individual, weak and strong. In Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory IV, ed. M. Harvey and L. Santelmann, 220–229. Ithaca: CLC Publications, Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1975. Adverbs of quantification. In Formal semantics of natural language, ed. E.L. Keenan, 3–15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice theoretic approach. In Meaning, use and interpretation of language, ed. R. Bauerle, C. Schwartze, and A. von Stechow, 302–323. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, F.H. 1990. Scope and dependency in English and Chinese. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, R. 1985. Logical form: Its structure and derivation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L. 1995a. Bare plurals in Spanish are interpreted as properties. In ed. G. Morrill and R. Oehrle, 197–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L. 1995b. Stativity and theticity. Columbus: Ms, Center for Cognitive Science, Ohio State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L. 1998. Existential sentences without existential quantification. Linguistics and Philosophy 31: 353–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNally, L., and V. van Geenhoven. 1998. Redefining the weak/strong distinction. Ms, Universitat Pompeu Fabra & Max Planck Institut Nijmegen, Barcelona/Nijmegen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milsark, G. 1977. Towards the explanation of certain peculiarities of existential sentences in English. Linguistic Analysis 3: 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. 1974. Formal philosophy. Selected papers of Richard Montague. Edited by R.H. Thomason, New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mostowski, A. 1957. On a generalization of quantifiers. Fundamenta Mathematicae 44: 12–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B.H. 1987. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers, ed. J. Groenendijk, D. de Jongh, and M. Stokhof, 115–144. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pesetsky, D. 1987. Wh-in-situ: Movement and unselective binding. In The representation of (in)definiteness, ed. E. Reuland and A. ter Meulen, 98–130. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, T. 1995. Interface strategies. OTS Working Papers, Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, T. 1997a. Quantifier scope. How labor is divided between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20: 335–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinhart, T. 1997b. Wh-in-situ in the framework of the minimalist program. Natural Language Semantics 6(1): 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. 1992. Types of plural individuals. Linguistics and Philosophy 15: 641–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steedman, M. 2003. Scope alternation and the syntax/semantics interface. Paris: CSSP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steedman, M. 2006. Surface-compositional scope-alternation without existential quantifiers. Ms available on http://homepages.inf.ed.ac.uk/steedman/papers.html.

  • Szabolcsi, A., ed. 1997. Ways of scope taking. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Geenhoven, V. 1996. Semantic incorporation and indefinite descriptions: Semantic and syntactic aspects of noun incorporation in West Greenlandic. Ph.D. dissertation, Tübingen. Published in 1998 by CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winter, Y. 1997. Choice functions and the scopal semantics of indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy 20: 399–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dobrovie-Sorin, C., Beyssade, C. (2012). Why Indefinites?. In: Redefining Indefinites. Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol 85. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-3002-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics