Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

The standard view of pains among philosophers today is that their existence consists in being experienced. The typical line of support offered for this view is that it corresponds with the ordinary or commonsense conception of pain. Despite this, a growing body of evidence from experimental philosophers indicates that the ordinary understanding of pain stands in contrast to the standard view among philosophers. In this paper, we will survey this literature and add to it, detailing the results of seven new studies on the ordinary understanding of pain using both questionnaire and corpus analysis methods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Reuter and Sytsma (ms) for further examples and an extended discussion, as well as Reuter (2017) for a critical challenge to the idea that the standard view can be squared with data from developmental studies.

  2. See Reuter et al. (2014) for further examples and an extended discussion.

  3. If this is correct, a further issue arises: Should we accept the deliverances of our intuitions with regard to the nature of pain? And to what extent should we treat these deliverances as being defeasible and open to revision in the light of theoretical considerations and/or empirical findings?

  4. For a brief introduction to experimental philosophy see Sytsma and Machery (2013). For extended introductions see Alexander (2012) and Sytsma and Livengood (2015). For collections of articles see Knobe and Nichols (2008, 2013), as well as the volumes in the Advances in Experimental Philosophy series. For discussions of some recent disputes see Machery and O’Neil (2014) and Sytsma (2017). And for an extensive survey of the state of the art of experimental philosophy see Sytsma and Buckwalter (2016).

  5. For a discussion of the difference between experiments, quasi-experiments, and descriptive studies see Sytsma and Livengood (2015, Chapter 5).

  6. For a recent survey, see Sytsma (2014a). For a short introduction to work in experimental philosophy of mind, see Machery and Sytsma (2011). For a more extended review, see Sytsma (2010a) and Sytsma and Livengood (2015). For a collection of cutting-edge articles, see Sytsma (2014b), as well as the section on “Philosophy of Mind” in Sytsma and Buckwalter (2016).

  7. These results have been replicated a number of times; see Sytsma and Machery (2012), Sytsma (2012) and Sytsma (2014c).

  8. Participants were asked whether the twins felt one and the same pain or two different pains, and answered on a 7-point scale anchored at 1 with “clearly same pain,” at 4 with “not sure,” and at 7 with “clearly different pains.” The mean response was 3.29, which was significantly below the neutral response of 4.

  9. Responses were collected through the Philosophical Personality website (http://philosophicalpersonality.com). Participants were counted as having more than minimal training in philosophy if they were philosophy majors, had completed a degree with a major in philosophy, or had taken graduate-level courses in philosophy. The participants were 71.6% women, with an average age of 35.0 years, and ranging in age from 16 to 86.

  10. 18 participants missed the comprehension check and were removed, although this had minimal effect on the results: including those participants, 67.5% (226/335) answered that the twins felt one and the same pain. Further, we saw no notable difference in responses based on the order in which they saw the probes: of those who got the comprehension check correct, 69.8% (90/129) of participants who got the shared pain probe first answered that the twins felt one and the same pain compared to 67.6% (127/188) of participants giving that answer when they got the painkiller probe first.

  11. χ 2(1, N = 317) = 42.4479, p < 0.001, one-tailed.

  12. 35 participants missed the comprehension check and were removed from the analysis, although this had minimal effect on the results: including those participants, 82.1% (275/335) selected the (a) answer. Again, there was no notable difference in responses based on the order in which they saw the probes: of those who got the comprehension check correct, 84.3% (102/121) of participants who got the shared pain probe first gave the (a) answer compared to 83.2% (149/179) of participants giving that answer when they got the painkiller probe first.

  13. χ 2(1, N = 300) = 134.67, p < 0.001, one-tailed.

  14. The participants were 73.2% women, with an average age of 37.2 years, and ranging in age from 16 to 76.

  15. 16 participants missed the comprehension check and were removed from the analysis, although this had minimal effect on the results: including those participants, 84.6% (126/149) selected the (a) answer.

  16. χ 2(1, N = 131) = 59.115, p < 0.001, one-tailed.

  17. The participants were 65.2% women, with an average age of 33.7 years, and ranging in age from 16 to 100.

  18. 12 participants missed the comprehension check and were removed from the analysis, although this had minimal effect on the results: including those participants, 65.2% (116/178) selected the (a) answer.

  19. χ 2(1, N = 166) = 15.6687, p < 0.001, one-tailed.

  20. The participants were 73.6% women, with an average age of 41.9 years, and ranging in age from 16 to 85.

  21. (1) t(109) = 5.9374, p < 0.001, one-tailed; (2) t(109) = 5.4726, p < 0.001, one-tailed; (3) t(109) = 2.4399, p = 0.008, one-tailed.

  22. The participants were 66.0% women, with an average age of 43.8 years, and ranging in age from 16 to 88.

  23. (1) t(102) = 2.1086, p = 0.019, one-tailed; (2) t(102) = 3.4327, p < 0.001, one-tailed; (3) t(102) = 1.5629, p = 0.061, one-tailed.

  24. The participants were 35.6% women, with an average age of 29.2 years, and ranging in age from 18 to 74. All participants were reimbursed for their participation.

  25. The percentage of “yes” responses was significantly above 50% in each case: (1) χ 2(1, N = 101) = 38.059, p < 0.001, one-tailed; (2) χ 2(1, N = 101) = 43.129, p < 0.001, one-tailed; (3) χ 2(1, N = 101) = 19.168, p < 0.001, one-tailed.

  26. For an introduction to corpus analysis and a discussion of its merits for and applications in philosophical research, see Bluhm (2015).

  27. Work on the commonsense conception of pain to date has largely focused on native English-speakers, but see Kim et al. (2016) for a cross-cultural study testing the views of South Koreans.

  28. While we would have liked to use a larger number of attributes for low-intensity pains, only the four mentioned in the main text yielded a sufficiently high number of hits.

  29. Please note that the plural form „Schmerzen“ (=pains) is much more frequently used in German compared to English.

  30. I-form, χ 2(1, N = 1019) = 103.99, p < 0.001; General Form, χ 2(1, N = 904) = 12.14, p = 0.001.

References

  • Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy: An introduction. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. (2005a). Preface. In M. Aydede (Ed.), Pain: New papers on its nature and the methodology of its study (pp. ix–xvii). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. (2005b). Introduction: A critical and quasi-historical essay on theories of pain. In M. Aydede (Ed.), Pain: New papers on its nature and the methodology of its study (pp. 1–58). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. (2009). Pain. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/pain/.

  • Bluhm, R. (2015). Corpus analysis in philosophy. In M. Hinton (Ed.), Evidence, experiment and argument in linguistics and the philosophy of language, Peter Lang (pp. 91–109).

  • Block, N. (2005). Bodily sensations as an obstacle for representationism. In M. Aydede (Ed.), Pain: New papers on its nature and the methodology of its study (pp. 137–142). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. (2009). Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, H., Poth, N., Reuter, K., & Sytsma, J. (2016). Where is your pain? A Cross-cultural comparison of the concept of pain in Americans and South Koreans. Studia Philosophica Estonica, 9(1), 136–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2008). Experimental philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2013). Experimental philosophy (Vol. 2). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). Mad pain and martian pain. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in the philosophy of psychology (pp. 216–222). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lund, F. H. (1926). The criteria of confidence. The American Journal of Psychology, 37(3), 372–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., & Sytsma, J. (2011). Robot pains and corporate feelings. The Philosophers’ Magazine, 1st Quarter, 78–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., O’Neill, E. (eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy, New York: Routledge.

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1963). Brains and behavior. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytic philosophy (2nd series) (pp. 211–235). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinton, A. M. (1956). The problem of perception. Mind, 64, 28–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuter, K. (2011). Distinguishing the appearance from the reality of pain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(9–10), 94–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuter, K (2017). The developmental challenge to the paradox of pain. Erkenntnis, 82(2), 265–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reuter, K., Phillips, D., & Sytsma, J. (2014). Hallucinating pain. In J. Sytsma (Ed.), Advances in experimental philosophy of mind. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reuter, K., & Sytsma, J. (ms). Unfelt pain.

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. (2009). Phenomenological obviousness and the new science of consciousness. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 958–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. (2010a). Folk psychology and phenomenal consciousness. Philosophy Compass, 5(8), 700–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. (2010b). Dennett’s theory of the folk theory of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17(3–4), 107–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J (2010c). Phenomenal Consciousness as Scientific Phenomenon? A Critical Investigation of the New Science of Consciousness. Ph.D. Dissertation. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh.

  • Sytsma, J. (2012). Revisiting the valence account. Philosophical Topics, 40(2), 179–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. (2014a). Attributions of consciousness. WIREs Cognitive Science, 5, 635–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, Justin. (2014b). Advances in experimental philosophy of mind. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, Justin. (2014c). The Robots of the dawn of experimental philosophy of mind. In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J. (2017). Two origin stories for experimental philosophy. Teorema, 36(3).

  • Sytsma, J., & Buckwalter, W. (2016). A companion to experimental philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2015). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2009). How to study folk intuitions about phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151(2), 299–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2012). On the relevance of folk intuitions: A reply to Talbot. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(2), 654–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2013). Experimental philosophy. In B. Kaldis (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy and the social sciences (pp. 318–320). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2005). Another look at representationalism about pain. In M. Aydede (Ed.), Pain: New papers on its nature and the methodology of its study (pp. 99–120). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Justin Sytsma.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sytsma, J., Reuter, K. Experimental Philosophy of Pain. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 34, 611–628 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0121-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0121-y

Keywords

Navigation