Skip to main content
Log in

Taming Fantastic Beasts of Mathematics: Struggling with Incommensurability

  • Published:
International Journal of Research in Undergraduate Mathematics Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to commognitive conceptualization, development of mathematical thinking, whether historical or ontogenetic, requires periodic transitions to mathematical discourse incommensurable with the one that has been practiced so far. In this new discourse, some familiar mathematical words will be used in a new way. Historically, such discursive transformations were usually greeted with resistance and led to heated, centuries-long debates. Also for today’s learners, a discourse incommensurable with the one currently in use constitutes a source of much trouble. This is particularly true in those cases in which the change in the use of words occurs tacitly, leading to apparent paradoxes. In this paper, I argue that discourses of finite and infinite sets are mutually incommensurable, and thus the case of students grappling with Sierpiński triangle (ST) may lead to insights about ways in which learners act in the face of incommensurability. Here, possible sources of the confusion reported by the participants are identified with the help of specially designed discourse-analytic tools. It is shown that the students, imperceptibly to themselves, oscillate between the discourses of area-as-a-segment-of-a-plane and of area-as-a-number. The analysis is followed with discussion on theoretical, methodological and practical implications of this study.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

adapted from Sfard, 2008)

Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Most current uses of the term story or narrative imply chronological interconnection of the different parts, and thus this definition leads to a wider understanding of this term than some readers may be used to.

  2. To avoid confusion, let me remark that in the work of some other authors (e.g. Radford, 2013), the word objectification is understood differently, and one should be wary of mistaking one for the other.

  3. Both italicized words, graph and tree, are used here in the sense in which they appear in the mathematical graph theory.

  4. In his later work, Kuhn himself tried to solve the problem of conceptual ambiguity by proposing languages as the objects that can be in the relation of incommensurability. If this proposal did not seem to work, it might be for reasons similar to those I presented above while explaining my preference for defining mathematics as discourse rather than language.

  5. This position has been presented in many different ways by the increasingly vocal and influential opponents of the postmodernist movement. It may be best reflected in the famous ‘Sokal hoax’ (Hilgartner, 1997).

  6. More precisely, perimeter and area are quantities, which are expressible in numbers of units, such as centimeter and square centimeter, respectively. By saying that for us area and perimeter are numbers, the intention is to stress the form in which the answer to the question ‘What is the area/perimeter?’ is usually given.

  7. To summarize, in this classroom the word area was sometimes used as standing for a concrete shape, and sometimes as a metonymy for such shape (the use is called metonymical if a word that signifies a property of an object is employed to signify the object as such).

  8. Note that the prefixes CS, N in the names of the discourses indicate the discourse-specific ontology of the objects denoted by the words area and perimeter. It is important to keep in mind that the three discourses include also objects other than those denoted by those prefixes, with those among them that are signified by the geometric names such as triangle (note that also the ontology of these latter, geometric objects is different from one of the discourses to another).

  9. In the full transcript of the session we did find a single use of the noun infinity: in SGW6, Joy said ‘Well, in one sense it's infinity, because you keep adding a little bit more’. However, even here, the hedge ‘in a sense’ shows her insecurity with regard to the use of this word.

  10. Because of the scarcity of instructor’s talk, we can only speculate on the extent to which this claim held for him as well. As argued by one of the reviewers of this paper, instructor’s questions such as "Can you assign an area to this shape?" "Can you assign a perimeter to this shape?" posed in the worksheet may signal his awareness to at least the incommensurability between N and AS discoruses.

References

  • Bachelard, G. (1938/1986). The Formation of the scientific mind: A contribution to a psychoanalysis of objective knowledge. Beacon Press.

  • Brousseau, G. (1983). Les obstacles épistémologiques et les problèmes en mathématique. Rech Didact Math, 4(2), 165–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brousseau, G. (1997). Theory of didactical situations in mathematics. Didactique des mathématiques 1970–1990. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Cantor, G. (1886). Zum Problem des actualen Unendlichen. Natur Und Offenbarung, 32, 225–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, R., & Easley, J. (1978). Pupils and paradigms: A review of literature related to concept development in adolescent science students. Studies in Science Education, 5, 61–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esmonde, I. (2009). Explanations in mathematics classrooms: A discourse analysis. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 9(2), 86–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, Paul (1975/2010). Against Method, 4th ed. Verso Books.

  • Fleck, L. (1935/1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact. Chicago University Press.

  • Gauss, C. F. (1877). Werke. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hilgartner, S. (Autumn 1997). The Sokal affair in context. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 22(4), 506–522. https://doi.org/10.1177/016224399702200404

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jasien, L., & Gresalfi, M. (2021). The role of participatory identity in learners’ hybridization of activity across contexts. Journal of the Learning Sciences 1–31 https://doi.org/10.1080/10508406.2021.1940186

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. ( 1976/2012). Proofs and refutations: The logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge University Press.

  • Moritz, R. E. (1914/1942). Memorabilia mathematica: The philomath's quotation book. The Mathematical Association of America, Spectrum.

  • Noether, E., & Cavaillès, J. (1937). Briefwechsel Cantor-Dedekind. Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970 ). Piaget’s theory. In P. H. Mussen (Ed.), Carmichael’s handbook of child psychology. Wiley.

  • Preston, J., Munévar, G., & Lamb, D. (Eds.) (2000). The worst enemy of science? Essays in memory of Paul Feyerabend. Oxford University Press.

  • Radford, L. (2013). Three key concepts of the theory of objectification: Knowledge, knowing, and learning. REDIMAT - Journal of Research in Mathematics Education, 2(1), 7–44. https://doi.org/10.17583/redimat.2013.570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, M. (2020). Epistemological obstacles in mathematics education. In S. Lerman (Ed.), Encyclopedia of mathematics education (pp. 276–279). Springer International Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sfard, A. (2008). Thinking as communicating: Human development, the growth of discourses, and mathematizing. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sfard, A. (2020). Learning, discursive fault lines, and dialogic engagement In N. Mercer, R. Wegerif, & L. Major (Eds.), The Routledge International Handbook of Research on Dialogic Education (pp. 89–99). Routledge.

  • Smith, J. P., diSessa, A. A., & Rochelle, J. (1993). Misconceptions reconceived: A constructivist analysis of knowledge in transition. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 3(2), 115–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Hiele, P. M. (1985). A child's thought and geometry. In D. Fuys, D. Geddes, & R. Tischler (Eds.), English translation of selected writing of Dina van Hiele-Geldorf and Pierre M. van Hiele (pp. 243–252), Brooklyn College, School of Education.

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1987). Thinking and speech. In R. W. Rieber & A. C. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L. S. Vygotsky (pp. 39–285). Plenum Press.

  • Wallace, D. F. (2010). Everything and more: A compact history of infinity. W. W. Norton & Company.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This special issue has been conceived at a workshop supported by the Israel Science Foundation under grant number 2821/19. The data described above and used in the papers in this special issue have been collected in the framework of research funded by the Israel Science Foundation under grant number 843/15. The author wishes to thank the Editors of this special issue for giving her the opportunity to engage with their work and have her own analytic take on their data.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anna Sfard.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of Interest

The author hereby declares that there is no conflict of interest related to this work.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Highlights

• Learning mathematics requires occasional transitions to a new mathematical discourse.

• The transition, while invisible to the learner, may produce narratives incommensurable with those the student endorsed so far.

• In the analyzed conversation, the students oscillated between two discourses of area strongly incommensurable with those of experts.

• To make the transition to the discourse of experts the students need first to reify infinity and limits.

• A conversation about incommensurability of the new discourse and about its history may help students cope with the transition.

Sfard, A. Taming fantastic beasts of mathematics: Struggling with incommensurability International Journal for Research in Undergraduate Mathematics Education.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sfard, A. Taming Fantastic Beasts of Mathematics: Struggling with Incommensurability. Int. J. Res. Undergrad. Math. Ed. 9, 572–604 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40753-021-00156-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40753-021-00156-7

Keywords

Navigation