Skip to main content
Log in

Environment as Abstraction

  • Thematic Issue Article: Conceptualizing the Environment in Natural Sciences
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The concept of the environment appears to be indispensably involved in adaptive explanation. Quite what its role is, however, is a matter of some dispute. The environment is customarily viewed as the dual of the organism; a wholly external, discrete, autonomous cause of evolution. On this view, the external environment is the principal cause of the adaptedness of form, and the determinant of what it is to be an adaptation. I argue that this conception of the environment neither adequately explains nor individuates evolutionary adaptations. Instead, adaptation, properly construed, is an evolutionary response to affordances. The environment, traditionally construed, underdetermines an organism’s affordances. Instead, I argue that the environment takes its place in evolutionary models not as a discrete causal entity, but as an abstraction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for example Godfrey-Godfrey-Smith (2001) and Lewontin (2002). Tim Lewens (2009) gives an insightful guide to various ways in which the concept of an adaptation may figure in evolutionary explanation.

  2. Trevor Pearce (2010) beautifully documents the emergence of this conception of the environment.

  3. This suggestion was first made in Walsh (2015). This article develops the argument adumbrated there.

  4. More recent contributions include Abrams (2014), Glymour (2011), and Rosenberg and Bouchard (2004). As I shall argue, below, the confusions concerning the role of the environment still persist.

  5. The types may be gene types or trait types. Note the constancy of the environment does not entail that it is homogeneous.

  6. For another example of the concept of the environment used in this way see Burian (1992).

  7. Similarly, Glymour (2011) argues, quite convincingly, that for certain purposes certain causally relevant features of the environment must be explicitly represented in our models.

  8. See also Gildenhuys (2014).

  9. Andrew Buskell (2019) has a helpful discussion of two grades of reciprocal causation. I thank an anonymous referee from this journal for making a helpful suggestion here.

  10. The example is taken from Sultan (2015).

  11. An organism’s internal features, structures, capacities, are relevant to the determination of its conditions too. An organism’s metabolic, immune, or endocrine state constitutes part of its experienced conditions.

  12. I thank Lynn Chiu for pressing this point.

  13. Contexts may here be environmental contexts, or the context provided other traits that an individual organism may possess.

  14. A somewhat similar argument is made by Grant Ramsey (2006) in support of the idea that the fitness of an organism ("block fitness") should be coarse-grained.

  15. But I do not agree with Glymour that the need to incorporate the environment in models salvages the concept of adaptation as adaptation to the environment.

References

  • Abrams M (2009) What determines fitness? The problem of the reference environment. Synthese 166(1):21–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrams M (2014) Environmental grain, organism fitness, and type fitness. In: Barker G, Desjardins E, Pearce T (eds) Entangled life. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 121–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Antonovics J, Ellstrand NC, Brandon RN (1988) Genetic variation and environmental variation: expectations and experiments. In: Gottlieb LD, Jain SK (eds) Plant evolutionary biology. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 275–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch J (2014) Has Grafen formalized Darwin? Commentary on Grafen’s ‘The Formal Darwinism project in outline.’ Biol Philos 29:175–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2007) Nature’s capacities. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1992) Environment. In: Keller EF, Lloyd E (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 81–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian R (1992) Adaptation: current usages. In: Keller EF, Lloyd E (eds) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Buskell A (2019) Reciprocal causation and the extended evolutionary synthesis. Biol Theor 14(4):267–279. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-019-00325-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiu L (2019) Decoupling, commingling, and the evolutionary significance of experiential niche construction. In: Uller T, Laland K (eds) Evolutionary causation: biological and philosophical reflections. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 299–322

    Google Scholar 

  • Danchin E, Pocheville A, Huneman P (2018) Early in life effects and heredity: reconciling neo-Darwinism with neo-Lamarkism under the banner of inclusive inheritance. Philos Trans R Soc B. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2018.0113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson JJ (1979) The ecological theory of perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Gildenhuys P (2014) Arbitrariness and causation in classical population genetics. Br J Philos Sci 65(3):429–444

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour B (2011) Modeling environments: interactive causation and adaptations to environmental conditions. Philos Sci 78(3):448–471

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2001) Organism, environment, and dialectics. In: Singh R, Krimbas C, Paul D, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 253–266

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1984) Natural selection, kin selection and group selection. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology, 2nd edn. Blackwell Scientific Publications, Oxford, pp 62–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (1998) Having thought: essays in the metaphysics of mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano M (2019) The philosophy of affordances. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano M (2020) The evolutionary role of affordances: ecological psychology, niche construction, and natural selection. Biol Philos 35:30. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09747-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herman JJ, Sultan S, Horgan-Kybelski T, Riggs C (2016) Adaptive transgenerational plasticity in an annual plant: grandparental and parental drought stress enhance performance of seedlings in dry soil. Integr Comp Biol 52:77–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Hu Y, Linz DM, Parker ES, Schwab DB, Casasa S, Macagno ALM, Moczeck AP (2019) Developmental bias in horned dung beetles and its contributions to innovation, adaptation, and resilience. Evol Dev 2019:1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2010) The mirage of a space between nature and nurture. Duke University Press, Durham

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland K, Sterelny K, Uller T, Hoppit FJ, Odling-Smee J (2016) The Extended Evolutionary Synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions Proc Biol Sci 282:2015109

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. In: Sober E (ed) Conceptual issues in revolutionary biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 18–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1978) Adaptation. Sci Am 239:212–230

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2002) Genes, organisms and environments. In: Oyama S, Griffiths EP, Gray R (eds) Cycles of contingency: developmental systems and evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 59–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and selection. J Philos 99:58–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2014) How the concept of population resolves the concept of the environment. Philos Sci 81(5):741–755

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee FJ, Laland K, Feldman M (2000) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr HA (2005) The genetic theory of adaptation: a brief history. Nat Rev Genet 6:119–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr HA (2006) Theories of adaptation: what they do and don’t say. Genetica 123:3–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr HA, Coyne JA (1992) The genetics of adaptation revisited. Am Nat 140:725–742

    Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka J, Turner TY, Allen C, Lloyd E (2011) Why the causal view of fitness survives. Philos Sci 78:209–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (2000) Evolution’s eye. Duke University Press, Durham

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce T (2010) From ‘circumstances’ to ‘environment’: Herbert Spencer and the origins of the idea of organism-environment interaction. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 41:241–252

    Google Scholar 

  • Purcell EM (1977) Life at low Reynolds number. Am J Phys 45:101–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey G (2006) Block fitness. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 37(3):484–498

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A, Bouchard F (2004) Fitness, probability, and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55:693–712

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar S (2014) Formal Darwinism: some questions. Biol Philos 29:249–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga J (2016) (2016) Population pluralism and natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 67:1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Stereleny K, Griffiths PE (1998) Sex and death. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sultan S (2015) Organisms and environment: ecological development, niche construction, and adaptation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sultan S (2019) Genotype-environment interactions and the unscripted reaction norm. In: Uller T, Laland K (eds) Evolutionary causation: biological and philosophical reflections. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 109–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Treratola M, Relli V, Simeone P, Alberti S (2015) Epigenetic inheritance and the missing heritability. Human Genomics 28:9. https://doi.org/10.1186/s40246-015-0041-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner JS (2001) The extended organism: the physiology of animal-built structures. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Waddington CH (1957) The strategy of the genes. Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner A (1999) Causality in complex systems. Biol Philos 14:83–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2012) Situated adaptationism. In: Kabesenche W, O’Rourke M, Slater M (eds) The environment: philosophy, science, ethics. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 89–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2014a) The negotiated organism: inheritance, development and the method of difference. Biol J Lin Soc 112:295–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2014b) Descriptions and models: some replies to Abrams. Stud Hist Philos Sci C 44:302–308

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2015) Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Ariew A, Matthen M (2017) Four pillars of statisticalism. Philos Theor Pract Biol 7:1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2006) Forty years of ‘The Strategy’: Levins on model building and idealization. Philos Biol 21:526–645

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther R, Giordano R, Edge M, Nielsen R (2015) The mind, the lab, and the field, three kinds of populations in scientific practice. Stud Hist Philos Sci C 52:12–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1931) Evolution in Mendelian populations. Genetics 16(2):97–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1938) Size of population and breeding structure in relation to evolution. Science 87:430–431

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Gaëlle Pontarotti and Antoine Corriveau-Dussault, and the audience at IHPST, Paris. I am grateful for the assistance of two anonymous referees from this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Denis Walsh.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Walsh, D. Environment as Abstraction. Biol Theory 17, 68–79 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-020-00367-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-020-00367-2

Keywords

Navigation