Skip to main content
Log in

Pliability and resistance: Feyerabendian insights into sophisticated realism

  • Original paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we focus on two claims, put forward by Feyerabend in his later writings (especially in Conquest of Abundance, 1999a), which constitute the metaphysical core of his view of scientific inquiry. The first, that we call the pliability thesis, is the claim that the world can be described by indefinitely many conceptual systems, none of them enjoying a privileged status. The second, that we call the resistance thesis, is the claim that the pliability of the world is limited, i.e., not all the different conceptual systems that can be used to describe the world will be equally successful: the world offers resistance to some attempts to describe it. We show that, in spite of the later Feyerabend’s notorious antirealist leanings, the pliability thesis is fully compatible with a robustly realist view of science, and we suggest that, surprisingly, Feyerabend’s insights concerning the limited pliability of the world turn out to be those of a potential ally of sophisticated versions of scientific realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A brief account of these diverging interpretations will be offered in Section 3.

  2. For discussions of the argument, and of the relevant literature, see e.g. Preston (1997), Ch. 7, and Farrell (2003), Ch. 5. On Feyerabend’s pluralism, see especially Lloyd (2000 [1997]).

  3. Along similar lines, Munévar has argued that the later Feyerabend defended a position “similar to Bohr’s: experiments, ideas, and models strongly interfere with nature, but they do not reveal how nature is independently of that interference—they only reveal how nature responds to that interference” (Munévar 2002, p. 520).

  4. Among the countless book-length discussions of realism see, e.g., Psillos (1999); Niiniluoto (1999); Kuipers (2000); Chakravartty (2007); Sankey (2008). It must be mentioned that the central commitments of realists can be formulated also in terms of (appropriately qualified versions of) the axiological thesis that science aims at discovering the truth about the world (see e.g. Lyons 2005 for a discussion of the axiological component of realism, and Rowbottom 2013 for a recent criticism of talk of the “aim of science” in general).

  5. Idealization, widely used in all fields of science, has been studied, among many others, by Krajewski (1977); Nowak (1980); McMullin (1985); Cartwright (1983, 1989).

  6. Pihlström et al. (2007) offers an extended discussion of Niiniluoto’s work.

  7. For discussions of Feyerabend’s pluralistic ideal of knowledge—which Niiniluoto (1999, p. 294) aptly defines “an extremely cumulativist account of science”—see, among others, Motterlini (2006) and Oberheim (2006).

  8. Relatedly, Niiniluoto’s critical scientific realism eschews relativism because all the conceptual systems used to describe the world are viewed as fragments of the same world, “and therefore cannot be incompatible with each other” (1999, p. 224).

  9. “Depending on the choice of a suitable conceptual framework,” Niiniluoto claims elsewhere, “THE WORLD can be ‘sliced’ or ‘structured’ to a system of a momentary events, mass points, physical systems, etc.” (1999, p. 222).

  10. Thanks are due to an anonymous reviewer for pressing this point. The same reviewer rightly notes that similar remarks apply also, more generally, to the pragmatist tradition in philosophy of science.

References

  • Brown, M. J. (2009). Models and perspectives on stage: remarks on Giere’s scientific perspectivism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 40, 213–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Cevolani, G., & Tambolo, L. (2013). Progress as approximation to the truth: a defence of the verisimilitudinarian approach. Erkenntnis, 78, 921–935.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2011). Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2011 edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/scientific-realism/. Retrieved on August 2nd, 2013.

  • Clark, S. R. L. (2002). Feyerabend’s Conquest of abundance. Inquiry, 45, 249–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downes, S. M. (2002). Review of Conquest of abundance. A tale of abstraction versus the richness of being, and The worst enemy of science? Essays in Memory of Paul Feyerabend. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 27, 160–164.

  • Farrell, R. P. (2003). Feyerabend and scientific values. Tightrope-walking rationality. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1962). Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 3, pp. 28–97). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1968). Outline of a pluralistic theory of knowledge and action. In S. Anderson (Ed.), Planning for diversity and choice (pp. 275–284). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1978). Science in a free society. London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1981 [1965]). Reply to criticism: comments on Smart, Sellars and Putnam. In P. K. Feyerabend, Realism, rationalism and scientific method. Philosophical papers, volume 1 (pp. 104–131). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge. Originally published in R. S. Cohen, & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1962-1964: In Honor of Philipp Frank (pp. 223–261). New York: Humanities Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1987). Farewell to reason. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1991). Three dialogues on knowledge. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1993). Against method (3rd ed.). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1999a). Conquest of abundance. A tale of abstraction versus the richness of being (Ed. by B. Terpstra). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1999b [1963]). How to be a good empiricist: A plea for tolerance in matters epistemological. In P. K. Feyerabend, Knowledge, science and relativism. Philosophical papers, volume 3 (Ed. by John Preston) (pp. 78–111). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.) Originally published In B. Baumrin (Ed.), Philosophy of Science: The Delaware Seminar (pp. 3–39). New York: Interscience Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1999c [1972]). On the limited valididy of methodological rules. (English translation of the German text by E. Oberheim and D. Sirtes, In P. K. Feyerabend, Knowledge, science and relativism. Philosophical papers, volume 3 (Ed. by J. Preston) (pp. 138–179). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.) Originally published as Von der beschränkten Gültigheit methodologischer Regeln. Neue Hefte für Philosophie, 2/3, 124–171.

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (2011). The Tyranny of science (Ed. by E. Oberheim). Cambridge: Polity Press

  • Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2012). Feyerabend, pseudo-Dionysius, and the ineffability of reality. Philosophia, 40, 365–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krajewski, W. (1977). Correspondence principle and the growth of knowledge. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (1987). A structuralist approach to truthlikeness. In T. A. F. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 79–99). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (2000). From instrumentalism to constructive realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (2000 [1997]). Feyerabend, Mill, and pluralism. In J. Preston, G. Munévar, & D. Lamb (Eds.), The worst enemy of science? Essays in memory of Paul Feyerabend (pp. 115–124). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Originally published in Philosophy of Science, 64, S396–S407.

  • Lyons, T. (2005). Towards a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63, 167–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 166–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Motterlini, M. (2006). Paul Karl Feyerabend. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), The philosophy of science. An encyclopedia (pp. 304–310). New York: Routledge.

  • Munévar, G. (2002). Critical notice: conquering Feyerabend’s Conquest of abundance. Philosophy of Science, 69, 519–535.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1984). Is science progressive? Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, L. (1980). The structure of idealization. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oberheim, E. (2006). Feyerabend’s philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pihlström, S., Raatikainen, P., & Sintonen, M. (Eds.). (2007). Approaching truth: Essays in honour of Ilkka Niiniluoto. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, J. (1997). Feyerabend: Philosophy, science, and society. Polity Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, J. (2000 [1998]). Science as supermarket: ‘Post-modern’ themes in Paul Feyerabend’s later philosophy of science. In J. Preston, G. Munévar, & D. Lamb (Eds.), The worst enemy of science? Essays in memory of Paul Feyerabend (pp. 80–101). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Originally published in Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 445–427.

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism. How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1994). Sense, nonsense and the senses: an inquiry into the powers of the human mind. The Journal of Philosophy, 91, 446–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. (2013). Aimless science. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0319-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2008). Scientific realism and the rationality of science. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1974). On Popper’s definition of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25, 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2011). Underdetermination, realism and empirical equivalence. Synthese, 180, 157–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper started life as a contributed talk delivered at the international conference “Feyerabend 2012,” wonderfully organized by Eric Oberheim and Matteo Collodel at the Humboldt-Universität, Berlin. I am grateful to the audience, and especially Karim Bschir, Ronald Giere, and Howard Sankey, for questions and suggestions, and to Ian James Kidd for his extensive written remarks on the text of my presentation. Thanks are due to Gustavo Cevolani, Roberto Festa, John Preston, and two anonymous reviewers for their comments on previous versions of the paper. Usual disclaimers apply. Financial support from PRIN grant “Probability, Confirmation and Verisimilitude” is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luca Tambolo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tambolo, L. Pliability and resistance: Feyerabendian insights into sophisticated realism. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 4, 197–213 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0082-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0082-9

Keywords

Navigation