Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Biosymbols: Symbols in Life and Mind

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The strong continuity thesis postulates that the properties of mind are an enriched version of the properties of life, and thus that life and mind differ in degree and not kind. A philosophical problem for this view is the ostensive discontinuity between humans and other animals in virtue of our use of symbols—particularly the presumption that the symbolic nature of human cognition bears no relation to the basic properties of life. In this paper, we make the case that a genuine account of strong continuity requires the identification of some sort of correlate of symbol-use in basic life properties. Our strategy is three-fold: 1) we argue that examples of proto-symbolism in simple living systems would be consistent with an evolutionary trajectory that ultimately produced symbolic cognition in humans; 2) we introduce Gordon Tomkins’ biological notion of ‘symbol’ as something that represents to the organism a feature of its environment that is significant to its survival; and 3) we employ this biological understanding of symbol-use to suggest that the symbolic nature of human cognition can be understood as an enriched version of the basic symbolic properties of life, thus preserving life-mind continuity in this context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Though Michael Wheeler notes in his 1997 paper that SCT is not meant to imply that life and mind are the same, since what we are after is “continuity and not equivalence”.

  2. An exemplar of which is Donald R. Griffin’s 1991 book, Cognitive Ethology: the minds of other animals.

  3. For example, a proponent of View A could argue that because non-human animals cannot think they are no different from inanimate objects and thus are not deserving of any sort of moral consideration.

  4. And here we distinguish human language from the various forms of animal communication.

  5. See Appendix.

  6. The Science Network’s interview with Dr. Vilayanur S. Ramachandran, Director of Brain and Cognition Institute at the University of California in San Diego: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=jTWmTJALe1w

References

  • Alberts, B., et al. (2002). Molecular biology of the cell (4th ed.). New York: Garland Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ames, B. N. (1977). Gordon M. Tomkins 1926–1975. In G. Litwack (Ed.), Biochemical actions of hormones (pp. xvii–xxxvi). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellman, K. L., & Goldberg, L. J. (1984). Common origin of linguistic and movement abilities. American Journal of Physiology, 246(Regulatory Integrative Comp. Physiol. 15), R915–R921.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Mindware. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Florida: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, W. T. (1997). The symbolic species: The co-evolution of language and the brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. M. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter of the mind. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (March 2006). Keynote address at the Harvard/MIT graduate philosophy conference.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996a). Complexity and the function of mind in nature. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996b). Spencer and Dewey on life and mind. In M. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial life (pp. 314–331). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D. R. (1991). Cognitive ethology: The minds of other animals. New Jersey: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble, W., & Davidson, I. (1996). Human evolution, language and mind: A psychological and archaeological inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pred, R. (2005). Onflow: Dynamics of consciousness and experience. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomkins, G. M. (Sept 5, 1975). The metabolic code. Science, New Series, Vol 189, No 4205, pp 760–763.

  • Wheeler, M. (1997). Cognition’s coming home: The reunion of life and mind. In I. Harvey & P. Husbands (Eds.), Proceedings of European conference on artificial life IV (pp. 10–19). London: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Liz Stillwaggon Swan.

Appendix

Appendix

Thus our working hypothesis is this: since evolution did in fact produce language-using organisms (us), and language is an enriched version of symbol-use, we should expect to find examples of proto-symbolism in simpler living systems. There is some evidence that Godfrey-Smith is amenable to such a hypothesis. He explains, “First, in humans we find not just first-order representation use, but a framework used to talk and think about representations. The empirical phenomenon of language and thought includes the existence of a framework that we use to describe, predict, influence, and manage the representation use of ourselves and others” (Godfrey-Smith 2006). This statement suggests that ‘first-order representation use’ is common to all life and that language is a unique human way of manipulating those (first-order) representations. Thus the use of first-order representation is important to many life forms including humans, and although humans may have a unique way of manipulating such representations, human language is not an anomaly in the natural world. And also: “The precursors of thought in non-human animals involve a low-level and comparatively “shallow” pattern of adjustment and transformation of environmental conditions. With the advent of language, the causal reach of these capacities is greatly extended and focused’ (Godfrey-Smith 2006). Human language use is seen as an enriched version of the ‘precursors of thought’ found in all life, in that it enriches our interaction with the world in ways unavailable to non-human life. Although (in the passage quoted in “Life-Mind Discontinuity”) Godfrey-Smith claims that life is “not ”proto-linguistic (Godfrey-Smith 1996b), we read the set of quotations above as suggesting that in fact certain “proto-cognitive” features in non-human life are to be understood as the biological precursors to human language use.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Swan, L.S., Goldberg, L.J. Biosymbols: Symbols in Life and Mind. Biosemiotics 3, 17–31 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-009-9066-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-009-9066-0

Keywords

Navigation