Skip to main content

George Henry Lewes (1817–1878): Embodied Cognition, Vitalism, and the Evolution of Symbolic Perception

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 6))

Abstract

To date, George Henry Lewes’ contributions to the intellectual culture of Victorian Britain have been overshadowed by the literary success of his partner, Marian Evans (better known by her pen name, George Eliot). In this chapter I draw attention to both the sophistication and continued relevance of Lewes’ writings on the mind-body problem, and particularly his five volume Problems of Life and Mind. I focus on three key arguments made by Lewes that remain relevant today: firstly, his rejection of extreme cerebrocentrism in favour of a view of the mind as embodied, i.e. that the somatic substrate of mind extends to regions of the body beyond the brain; secondly, that there is a qualitative difference between the ‘incalculable’ mechanisms of living creatures, and those of machines; and, thirdly, that our capacity for Ideation (or symbolic thought) and our concomitant immersion in the ‘Social Medium’ (or culture) are defining and characteristic features of humankind.

The history of science is the science itself: the history of the individual, the individual

Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Mineralogie und Geologie (‘Die Geschichte der Wissenschaft ist die Wissenschaft selbst, die Geschichte des Individuums das Individuum’, Goethe 1833, 130)

Our world of Thought is a strange mixture of truth and fiction,—of Experience condensed in symbols, and of inferences deduced from symbols, and taken for reals; but the advance of Humanity tends more and more to enlarge the fund of truths, and to disclose the pitfalls on its path. The history of the race is but that of the individual “writ large.”

George Henry Lewes, Problems of Life and Mind (Lewes 1875, 119)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Shuttleworth 1984; A Ryan 2011; V Ryan 2012.

  2. 2.

    There are a few notable exceptions, particularly Kaminsky 1952; Rylance 2000, 2004; and Tjoa 1977.

  3. 3.

    Lewes 1874, vi.

  4. 4.

    Stichweh 2001. Lewes was among the first to use the term ‘discipline’ in English in this context. Lewes 1874, p. 71. Lewes was not shy of introducing and promoting new terms and understandings. He has been credited with being the first Englishman to employ the terms ‘psychodynamic’ (Hearnshaw 1964), ‘personality’ (Rylance 2000) ‘and ‘stream of consciousness’ (Holland 1986) in ways comparable to the present day use.

  5. 5.

    Lewes 1873, 1876a, b, c, 1877a, 1878.

  6. 6.

    Tansey 1990, 1992.

  7. 7.

    Ballantyne 1994.

  8. 8.

    E.g., ‘All germinal conceptions are the product of their age rather than of any individual mind’, Lewes 1874, 84.

  9. 9.

    Lewes 1845, 1853. Lewes corresponded with Comte, and helped to bring his works to the attention of the English speaking public—including the first anglicized use of Comte’s neologism, ‘altruisme’.

  10. 10.

    Lewes 1874, viii.

  11. 11.

    Rylance 2004; Edelman 1994.

  12. 12.

    Fields 2009; Koob 2009. In the 1870s, at a time when his contemporaries were locked in debate over whether glia were neurons or connective tissue, Lewes disparaged this question as one that had been elevated to ‘undue importance because it is supposed to carry with it physiological consequences which would deprive the neuroglia of active cooperation in neural processes, reducing it to the insignificant position of a mechanical support. I cannot but regard this as due to the mistaken tendency of analytical interpretation, which somewhat arbitrarily fastens on one element in a complex of elements, and assigns that one as the sole agent’ Lewes 1877b, 246.

  13. 13.

    Lewes 1879a, ix.

  14. 14.

    Lewes 1879b, v.

  15. 15.

    Prinz 2009.

  16. 16.

    E.g. See Wilson 2002; Clark 2009; Robbins and Aydede 2009.

  17. 17.

    As paraphrased in The Times ‘Law Report’, for the 25 and 27 March, 1822. For more on the Lawrence-Abernethy controversy, see Temkin 1963; Goodfield-Toulmin 1969; Butler 1993; and Price 2012.

  18. 18.

    Yolton 1984; Price 2012.

  19. 19.

    For theories of the nerves, see Rousseau 1991a, b.

  20. 20.

    Shapin 1975; Cooter 1984.

  21. 21.

    Lewes 1877b, 188.

  22. 22.

    This tradition was pioneered at the start of the century by the London surgeon, William Lawrence and the followers of Franz Josef Gall, whose system of Organology (now better known as phrenology) held that not only intellect, but also emotions, mental illness, and will to be consubstantial with the brain. Price 2012.

  23. 23.

    Lewes 1874, 160–163. Gould 1981 presented a fascinating treatment of the history of craniometry and racism in Mismeasure of Man, although he does not consider the possibility raised here by Lewes—that not only was craniometry used to lend support to racism, but similarly racist prejudices conversely lent support to the adoption of the belief that that brain is the organ of mind.

  24. 24.

    Lewes 1879a, 19–27. For a historical treatment of the reflex (although not Lewes’ critique of it) see Clarke and Jacyna 1987, 101–156.

  25. 25.

    Lewes 1879a, 23.

  26. 26.

    Lewes 1879b, 150.

  27. 27.

    Lewes 1879a, 20.

  28. 28.

    Lewes 1874, 112: italics in original.

  29. 29.

    Lewes 1874, 96.

  30. 30.

    Lewes 1874, 110–111. Like his notion of sensibility, Lewes’ materialist vitalism echoes theories expressed in the eighteenth century, most prominently by French physiologists such as Bordeu, La Mettrie and Bichat. See Haigh 1976 and Kaitaro 2008.

  31. 31.

    Lewes 1874, 46.

  32. 32.

    Lewes 1877b, 324.

  33. 33.

    Lewes 1877b, 307–310. I have adopted the phrase ‘psycho-physiologists’ from Danziger 1982.

  34. 34.

    Daston 1978; Gray 1968; Greenwood 2010; Smith 2007.

  35. 35.

    Lewes 1877b, 188.

  36. 36.

    Lewes 1877b, 324–325.

  37. 37.

    Menke 2000.

  38. 38.

    Lewes 1874, v.

  39. 39.

    Lewes 1879b, 484.

  40. 40.

    Lewes 1879a, 119–121. Lewes was quite possibly the first to use ‘anthropomorphic’ in this modern sense, in his Sea-side Studies of 1858: c.f., Ashton 1991, 187.

  41. 41.

    Lewes 1879b, 489–490.

  42. 42.

    Vignoli 1885, 135–154.

  43. 43.

    Lewes was an early supporter of Darwin’s theory of natural selection – cf. Ashton 1991, 243–245.

  44. 44.

    Lewes 1874, 109.

  45. 45.

    Lewes 1874, 124.

  46. 46.

    Read 1881, 498.

  47. 47.

    James 1890, 5.

  48. 48.

    Lewes 1874, 120–121.

  49. 49.

    See Huw Price (no relation) 1996 and Zeh 2007. Contrary to popular belief, temporal symmetry can also be argued for second law of thermodynamics, which is often taken to be archetypal directional law—see Jos Uffink 2001. Temporal asymmetry has been reported at the subatomic level in k-mesons (Angelopoulos et al. 1998) and b-mesons (Lees et al. 2012) yet it remains to be seen how or whether this relates to the macroscopic/subjective arrow of time.

  50. 50.

    Fleck 1979.

  51. 51.

    See Christiansen and Kirby 2003, especially the chapters by Bickerton (who refers to Irene Pepperberg’s famous research on the capacities of parrots) and Davidson. Study of the evolutionary origins of language, as an academic discipline, is a relatively young field. However, as a subject of study, it is older than its advocates appear to realize. In recent works on the subject it has repeatedly been asserted that speculation on the evolutionary origins of language was brought to a halt (for 100 years) in 1866 by a proclamation of the Parisian Linguistic Society (e.g. Deacon 1997; Christiansen and Kirby 2003). Gregory Radick’s historical account of research on primate language very effectively (if unintentionally) overturns this assertion: Radick 2007.

  52. 52.

    Chalmers 1996, vii. See also Chalmers 1995.

  53. 53.

    Lewes 1874, 101.

  54. 54.

    Lewes 1874, 100.

  55. 55.

    Libet et al. 1983, 2004; Tallis 2011.

  56. 56.

    Lewes 1879b, 111.

  57. 57.

    Wozniak 1992, 12.

  58. 58.

    Lewes 1879b, 149.

  59. 59.

    Lewes 1874, 3.

References

  • Angelopoulos A, Angelos A, Apostolakis E, Aslanides E, Backenstoss G, Bargassa P, Behnke O, Benelli A et al (1998) First direct observation of time-reversal non-invariance in the neutral-kaon system. Phys Lett B 444(1):43–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashton R (1991) G. H. Lewes: a life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ballantyne PF (1994) G. H. Lewes: early reviews to mid-20th century obscurity. http://www.comnet.ca/~pballan/LEWES.htm. Viewed and archived on 28 Aug 2010 using WebCite® at http://www.webcitation.org/5sK1Jzaf9

  • Butler M (ed) (1993) Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein, or, the modern Prometheus: the 1818 text. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter WB (1874) Principles of mental physiology. H. S. King & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter WB (1875) The doctrine of human automatism. Sunday Lecture Society, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (1995) Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 2:200–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen MH, Kirby S (eds) (2003) Language evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2009) Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is probably. Still in the head. Mind 118:963–993

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke E, Jacyna LS (1987) Nineteenth-century origins of neuroscientific concepts. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford WK (1874) Body and mind. Reprinted in: Stephen L, Pollock F (eds) (1886) Lectures and essays. Macmillan, London, pp 244–273

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooter R (1984) The cultural meaning of popular science: phrenology and the organisation of consent in nineteenth-century Britain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotterill R (1998) Enchanted looms: conscious networks in brains and computers. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger K (1982) Mid-nineteenth-century British psycho-physiology: a neglected chapter in the history of psychology. In: Woodward WR, Ash MG (eds) The problematic science: psychology in nineteenth-century thought. Praeger, New York, pp 119–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston LJ (1978) British responses to psycho-physiology, 1860–1900. Isis 69:192–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deacon T (1997) The symbolic species: the co-evolution of language and the brain. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon T (2011) Incomplete nature: how mind emerged from matter. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald M (1991) Origins of the modern mind: three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald M (2001) A mind so rare: the evolution of human consciousness. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas Fields R (2009) The other brain: from dementia to schizophrenia, how new discoveries about the brain are revolutionizing medicine and science. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Duncan G (1869) The various theories of the relation of mind and brain reviewed. Trübner & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman G (1994) Bright air, brilliant fire: on the matter of the mind. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck L (1979) The genesis and development of a scientific fact. Edited by Trenn TJ, Merton RK; Foreword by Kuhn T. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Goethe JF (1833) Goethe’s Nachgelassene Werke. Cotta, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodfield-Toulmin J (1969) Some aspects of English physiology: 1780–1840. J Hist Biol 2:283–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1981) The mismeasure of man. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray PH (1968) Prerequisite to an analysis of behaviorism: the conscious automaton theory from Spalding to William James. J Hist Behav Sci 4:365–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood J (2010) Whistles, bells, and cogs in machines: Thomas Huxley and epiphenomenalism. J Hist Behav Sci 46:276–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haigh EL (1976) Vitalism, the soul, and sensibility: the physiology of Théophile Bordeu. J Hist Med All Sci 31:30–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hearnshaw LSA (1964) Short history of British psychology, 1849–1940. Barnes & Noble, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland JG (1986) George Henry Lewes and ‘stream of consciousness’: the first use of the term in English. South Atl Rev 51:31–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley S (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley TH (1874) On the hypothesis that animals are automata, and its history. Fortnightly Review 22:555–580. Reprinted in Collected essays: Vol I, Method and results. Macmillan, London, pp 195–250, 1893

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1879) Are we Automata? Mind 13:1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1890) The principles of psychology. Macmillan, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaitaro T (2008) Can matter mark the hours? Eighteenth-century vitalist materialism and functional properties. Sci Context 21:581–592

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminsky J (1952) The empirical metaphysics of George Henry Lewes. J Hist Idea 13:314–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koob A (2009) The root of thought: unlocking glia—the brain cell that will help us sharpen our wits, heal injury, and treat brain disease. FT Press, Upper Saddle River

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence W (1819) Lectures on physiology, zoology and the natural history of man. Longman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lees JP, Poireau V, Tisserand V, Garra Tico J, Grauges E, Palano A, Eigen G et al (2012) Observation of time-reversal violation in the B0 meson system. Phys Rev Lett 109(21):211801

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1845–1846) A biographical history of philosophy, 2 vols. Charles Knight & Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1853) Comte’s philosophy of the sciences: being an exposition of the principles of the Cours de Philosophie positive of Auguste Comte. HG Bohn, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1855) The life and works of Goethe. D. Nutt, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1858) Sea-side studies at Ilfracombe, Tenby, the Scilly isles, & Jersey. W. Blackwood, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1859–1860) Physiology of common life, 2 vols. W. Blackwood, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1873) Sensation in the spinal cord. Nature 9:83–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1874) Problems of life and mind first series: the foundations of a creed, vol I. Trübner & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1875) Problems of life and mind first series: the foundations of a creed, vol II. Trübner & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1876a) Review of F. Lussana and A. Lemoigite, Fisiologia dei Oentri Nervosi Encefalici. Mind 1:122–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1876b) Review of Ferrier’s functions of the brain. Nature 12, Nov 23 & Nov 30

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1876c) The uniformity of nature. Mind 2:283–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1877a) Consciousness and unconsciousness. Mind 6:157–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1877b) Problems of life and mind second series: the physical basis of mind. Trübner & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1878) Motor feelings and the muscular sense. Brain 1:14–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1879a) Problems of life and mind: third series: the study of psychology. Its object, scope, and method. Houghton, Osgood and Co., Boston

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1879b) Problems of life and mind: mind as a function of the organism. The sphere of sense and logic of feeling. The sphere of intellect and logic of signs. Trübner & co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet B (2004) Mind time: the temporal factor in consciousness. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet B, Gleason CA, Wright EW, Pearl DK (1983) Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity readiness-potential. The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106:623–642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandik P (1999) Qualia, space, and control. Philos Psychol 12:47–60

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudsley H (1880) The physical basis of will. Sunday Lecture Society, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Menke R (2000) Fiction as vivisection: G. H. Lewes and George Eliot. ELH 67:617–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë A (2005) Action in perception. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan JK, Noë A (2001) A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 24:939–1031

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price H (1996) Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point: new directions for the physics of time. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Price EH (2012) Do brains think? Comparative anatomy and the end of the Great Chain of Being in 19th-century Britain. Hist Hum Sci 25(3):32–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2009) Is consciousness embodied? In: Robbins P, Aydede M (eds) Cambridge handbook of situated cognition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Radick G (2007) The simian tongue: the long debate about animal language. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Read C (1881) G. H. Lewes’s Posthumous volumes. Mind 6:483–498

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins P, Aydede M (eds) (2009) Cambridge handbook of situated cognition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau GS (1991a) Nerves, spirits and fibres: towards an anthropology of sensibility. In: Rousseau GS (ed) Enlightenment crossings: pre- and post-modern discourses: anthropological. Manchester University Press, Manchester, pp 122–141

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau GS (1991b) Towards a semiotics of the nerve. In: Burke P, Porter R (eds) Language, self and society: the social history of language. Polity Press, Cambridge, pp 213–275

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan AE (2011) Victorian fiction and the psychology of self-control, 1855–1885. Doctor of Philosophy, Case Western Reserve University, English, 2011

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan VL (2012) Thinking without thinking in the Victorian novel. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Rylance R (2000) Victorian psychology and British culture 1850–1880. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rylance R (2004) Convex and concave: conceptual boundaries in psychology, now and then but mainly then. Vic Lit Cult 32:449–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin S (1975) Phrenological knowledge and the social structure of early nineteenth-century Edinburgh. Ann Sci 32:219–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shuttleworth S (1984) George Eliot and nineteenth century science. The make-believe of a beginning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith CUM (2007) William Carpenter and the Debate on Human Automatism in mid-Victorian England. In: Proceedings of the international society for the history and social studies of biology, 2007. University of Exeter, Exeter

    Google Scholar 

  • Spalding D (1877) Review of problems of life and mind. Nature 10:261–263, August 2

    Google Scholar 

  • Stichweh R (2001) History of scientific disciplines. In: Smelser NJ, Baltes PB (eds) International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences. Elsevier, Oxford, pp 13727–13731. Online at http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/03187-9

  • Tallis R (2011) Aping mankind: Neuromania, Darwinitis and the misrepresentation of humanity. Acumen Publishing, Durham

    Google Scholar 

  • Tansey EM (1990) George Eliot’s support for physiology: the George Henry Lewes trust 1879–1939. Note Rec Roy Soc Lond 44(2):221–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tansey EM (1992) “… the science least adequately studied in England”: physiology and the George Henry Lewes studentship, 1879–1939. J Hist Med All Sci 47(2):163–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Temkin O (1963) Basic science, medicine, and the romantic era. Bull Hist Med 37:97–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E, Varela FJ (2001) Radical embodiment: neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci 5:418–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tjoa HG (1977) George Henry Lewes: a Victorian mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyndall J (1874) Address delivered before the British Association assembled at Belfast: with additions. Longmans, Green and Company, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Uffink J (2001) Bluff your way in the second law of thermodynamics. Stud Hist Phil Mod Phys 32:305–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vignoli T (1885) Myth and science: an essay, 3rd edn. Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson M (2002) Six views of embodied cognition. Psychon Bull Rev 9:625–636

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wozniak RH (1992) Mind and body: René Descartes to William James. National Library of Medicine/American Psychological Association, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Yolton JW (1984) Thinking matter: materialism in eighteenth-century Britain. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeh HD (2007) The physical basis of the direction of time, 5th edn. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elfed Huw Price .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Price, E.H. (2014). George Henry Lewes (1817–1878): Embodied Cognition, Vitalism, and the Evolution of Symbolic Perception. In: Smith, C., Whitaker, H. (eds) Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8774-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics