Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Does Neuroscience Undermine Deontological Theory?

  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Joshua Greene has argued that several lines of empirical research, including his own fMRI studies of brain activity during moral decision-making, comprise strong evidence against the legitimacy of deontology as a moral theory. This is because, Greene maintains, the empirical studies establish that “characteristically deontological” moral thinking is driven by prepotent emotional reactions which are not a sound basis for morality in the contemporary world, while “characteristically consequentialist” thinking is a more reliable moral guide because it is characterized by greater cognitive command and control. In this essay, I argue that Greene does not succeed in drawing a strong statistical or causal connection between prepotent emotional reactions and deontological theory, and so does not undermine the legitimacy of deontological moral theories. The results that Greene relies on from neuroscience and social psychology do not establish his conclusion that consequentialism is superior to deontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although I will employ both philosophical arguments and empirical data, I am not qualified to explore some potential problems, such as disputes about the functions of different areas of the brain [28], or claims that Greene offers an inadequate model of moral decision-making because his discussion does not include any computational theory regarding moral perception [29]. I will also pass over some philosophical issues, such as whether Greene’s argument really counts against all deontology or only rationalist deontology [30].

  2. For a survey of some background sources on the reason/emotion distinction, see [24].

  3. The sets of dilemmas used in [2], [5], and [6] are almost identical, with one impersonal moral dilemma (“eyes”) omitted from [5] and with some variations among the core set of personal dilemmas in the three papers. The personal moral dilemmas were also used by Koenigs, et al. in [7], with some omissions.

  4. Greene seems to have recently modified his position regarding exactly “what features of an action elicit [emotional] response” [31: 365] but the core idea that deontological judgments are motivated by “negative emotional response” is the same [31: 365].

  5. For convenience in quoting Greene, I will follow his practice of using “utilitarian” and “consequentialist” interchangeably.

  6. The “eyes” story appears in [2] and [6], but is missing from [5].

  7. Also see the supplementary material, p. 2, at www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/0900152106/DCSupplemental

  8. Frances Kamm is a striking example.

  9. For a sophisticated discussion of a possible analogy between an innate, automatic, but not emotional linguistic faculty and a similar faculty for morality, see [32].

  10. For a survey of the literature, see [24].

  11. Moore et al. [19] does not involve fMRI neuroimaging, but nevertheless has results relevant to discussion of the role of different types of neural activity.

References

  1. Greene, Joshua. 2008. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Moral psychology, volume 3, the neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 35–79. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Greene, Joshua, Brian R. Sommerville, Leigh Nystrom, John Darley, and Jonathan D. Cohen. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293: 2105–2108. Supplementary descriptions of dilemmas available at: www.sciencemag.org/cgi/content/full/sci;293/5537/2105/DC1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Greene, Joshua. 2009. Dual-process morality and the personal/impersonal distinction: a reply to McGuire, Langdon, Coltheart, and Mackenzie. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45: 581–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. McGuire, Jonathan, Robyn Langdon, Max Coltheart, and Catriona Mackenzie. 2009. A reanalysis of the personal/impersonal distinction in moral psychology research. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45: 577–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Greene, Joshua, Leigh E. Nystrom, Andrew D. Engell, John M. Darley, and Jonathan D. Cohen. 2004. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44: 389–400. Supplementary description of dilemmas available at: www.neuron.org/cgi/content/full/44/2/389/DC1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Greene, Joshua, Sylvia A. Morelli, Kelly Lowenberg, Leigh E. Nystrom, and Jonathan D. Cohen. 2008. Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition 107: 1144–1154. Supplementary description of dilemmas available at: https://mcl.wjh.harvard.edu/materials/Greene-CogLoadSupMats.pdf.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Koenigs, Michael, Liane Young, Ralphs Adolphs, Daniel Tranel, Fiery Cushman, Marc Hauser, and Antonio Damasio. 2007. Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgments. Nature 446: 908–911. Supplemental description of dilemmas available: doi: 10.1038/nature05631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Greene, Joshua. 2003. From neural ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: what are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology? Nature Reviews, Neuroscience 4: 847–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Gazzaniga, Michael and Jonathan Le Doux. 1978. The Integrated Mind. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Haidt, Jonathan. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108(4): 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Nisbett, Richard and Timothy Wilson. 1977. Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84: 231–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Tetlock, Philip, Randall Peterson, and Jennifer Lerner. 1996. Revising the value pluralism model: Incorporating social content and context postulates. In Ontario symposium on social and personality psychology: Values, ed. C. Seligman, J. Olson, and M. Zanna. Hillsdale: Earlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Bartels, Daniel. 2007. Principled moral sentiment and the flexibility of moral judgment and decision making. Cognition 108: 381–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The metaphysics of morals. (Trans: Mary Gregor, from Die Metaphysik der Sitten, vol. vi of Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, 203–491). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  15. Kant, Immanuel. 2002. Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. (Translated and edited by Thomas Hill, Jr. and Arnulf Zweig, from Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, vol. iv of Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften, 387–463). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  16. Ross, William David. 2003. The right and the good. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Schaich Borg, Jana, Catherine Hynes, John Van Horn, Scott Grafton, and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. 2006. Consequences, action, and intention as factors in moral judgments: an fMRI investigation. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 18(5): 803–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Greene, Joshua and Joseph Paxton. 2009. Patterns of neural activity associated with honest and dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 106(30): 12506–12511. Supplementary materials available at: http://www.pnas.org/cgi/content/full/0900152106/DCSupplemental.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Moore, Adam, Brian Clark, and Michael Kane. 2008. Who shalt not kill? Individual differences in working memory capacity, executive control, and moral judgment. Psychological Science 19(6): 549–557. Supplementary description of dilemmas is available at www.uncg.edu/~mjkane/memlab.html.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Kant, Immanuel. 1965. Critique of pure reason (Trans: Norman Kemp-Smith from Kritik der Reinen Vernunft). New York: St. Martin’s.

  21. Greene, Joshua. 2008. Reply to Mikhail and Timmons. In Moral psychology, volume 3, the neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 105–117. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Valdesolo, Piercarlo and David DeSteno. 2006. Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychological Science 17(6): 476–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Luce, Mary, James Bettman, and John Payne. 1997. Choice processing in emotionally difficult decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition 23: 384–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Monin, Benoît, David Pizarro, and Jennifer Beer. 2007. Deciding versus reacting: conceptions of moral judgment in the reason-affect debate. Review of General Psychology 11(2): 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Tetlock, Philip, Orie Kristel, Beth S. Elson, Melanie Green, and Jennifer Lerner. 2000. The psychology of the unthinkable: taboo trade-offs, forbidden base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 78: 853–870.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Haidt, Jonathan, Silvia Helena Koller, and Maria G. Dias. 1993. Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65(4): 613–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Koenigs, Michael and Daniel D. Tranel. 2007. Irrational economic decision-making after ventromedial prefrontal damage: evidence from the ultimatum game. Neuroscience 27: 951–956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Moll, Jorge and Ricardo de Oliveira-Souza. 2007. Moral judgments, emotions, and the utilitarian brain. Trends in Cognitive Science 11(8): 319–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Mikhail, John. 2008. Moral cognition and computational theory. In Moral psychology, volume 3, the neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 81–91. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Timmons, Mark. 2008. Toward a sentimentalist deontology. In Moral psychology, volume 3, the neuroscience of morality: emotion, brain disorders, and development, ed. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, 93–104. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Greene, Joshua, Fiery Cushman, Lisa Stewart, Kelly Lowenberg, Leigh Nystrom, and Jonathan Cohen. 2009. Pushing moral buttons: the interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111(3): 364–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Hauser, Marc. 2006. Moral minds: How nature designed a universal sense of right and wrong. New York: Echo/ Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Dean.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dean, R. Does Neuroscience Undermine Deontological Theory?. Neuroethics 3, 43–60 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-009-9052-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-009-9052-x

Keywords

Navigation