Skip to main content
Log in

Lewis’ Reduction of Modality

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I start by reconsidering two familiar arguments against modal realism. The argument from epistemology relates to the issue whether we can infer the existence of concrete objects by a priori means. The argument from pragmatics purports to refute the analogy between the indispensability of possible worlds and the indispensability of unobserved entities in physical science and of numbers in mathematics. Then I present two novel objections. One focusses on the obscurity of the notion of isolation required by modal realism. The other stresses the arbitrary nature of the rules governing the behaviour of Lewisean universes. All four objections attack the reductive analysis of modality that is supposed to be the chief merit of modal realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Lewis (1986:94–6).

  2. See Lewis (1986:2,73) and Bigelow and Pargetter (1987:106–7).

  3. See Russell (1937:xvii).

  4. See e.g. Stalnaker (1996).

  5. See Lewis (1986:112).

  6. See McGinn (1981).

  7. This move is made by neo-Fregeans in the debate over mathematical platonism. See Hale and Wright (2001:321).

  8. Hinted in Skyrms (1976:326).

  9. This point is forcefully made by Bueno and Shalkowski (2000).

  10. Though it is of course revolting for a nominalist. The latter may well argue that mathematical practice does pose a genuine problem to be resolved through work on mathematical ontology. See Bueno and Shalkowski (2000).

  11. See Lewis (1986:74–76).

  12. See Lewis (1986:76).

  13. A notable exception is Rosenberg (1989).

  14. See Lewis (1986:71–73).

  15. See Earman (1970:267).

  16. See Strominger (1991). See also Rucker (1984) for a different approach.

  17. An alternative way of putting essentially the same idea could be this. According to modal realism, there are Newtonian worlds and there are relativistic worlds. Thus consider two possible worlds W n and W n containing a three-dimensional Newtonian space E 3 and a one-dimensional Newtonian time ℝ, and a possible world W r containing a relativistic spacetime like S 3 ×ℝ. We must first explain how there can be more than one Newtonian world, since this presumably will mean amending several key elements of Newtonian physics, such as the postulate of absolute simultaneity. After we are done with that, we will have to explain how all three worlds are isolated. But whatever form our theory of isolation will take, there is simply no reason to expect that isolation be physically invariant: the isolation of W n and W n will have to be explained differently from the isolation of W n and W r .

  18. See Bricker (2001).

  19. See Divers (2002:47–9).

  20. See Divers (2002:307).

  21. One should recall here the quandary Leibniz faced with his claim that God necessarily creates the best possible world. I discuss it at some length elsewhere.

References

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1987). Beyond the blank stare. Theoria, 53, 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2001). Island universes and the analysis of modality. In G. Preyer & F. Siebelt (Eds.), Reality and humean supervenience. Rowman and Littlefield.

  • Bueno, O., & Shalkowski, S. A. (2000). A plea for a modal realist epistemology. Acta Analytica, 15, 175–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Divers, J. (2002). Possible worlds. Routledge.

  • Earman, J. (1970). Space-time, or how to solve philosophical problems and dissolve philosophical muddles without really trying. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 259–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B., Wright, C. J. G. (2001). The reason’s proper study. Clarendon Press.

  • King, P. (1995). Other times. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73, 532–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell.

  • McGinn, C. (1981). Modal reality. In R. Healey (Ed.), Reduction, time, and reality (pp. 143–88). Cambridge University Press.

  • Quinton, A. M. (1962). Spaces and times. Philosophy, 37 130–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1989). Is Lewis’ “genuine modal realism” magical too? Mind, 98, 411–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucker, R. (1984). The fourth dimension. Houghton Mifflin.

  • Russell, B. A. W. (1937). A critical exposition of the philosophy of Leibniz (2nd ed.). Allen & Unwin.

  • Skyrms, B. (1976). Possible worlds, physics, and metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 30, 323–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (1996). On what possible worlds could not be. In A. Morton & S. Stich (Eds.), Benacerraf and his critics. Blackwell.

  • Strominger, A. (1991). Baby universes. In Quantum cosmology and baby universes. World Scientific.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to John Divers, Dorothy Edgington, Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra, and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on earlier versions of this material.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sandy Berkovski.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Berkovski, S. Lewis’ Reduction of Modality. Acta Anal 26, 95–114 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0070-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0070-4

Keywords

Navigation