Skip to main content
Log in

Must cognition be representational?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In various contexts and for various reasons, writers often define cognitive processes and architectures as those involving representational states and structures. Similarly, cognitive theories are also often delineated as those that invoke representations. In this paper, I present several reasons for rejecting this way of demarcating the cognitive. Some of the reasons against defining cognition in representational terms are that doing so needlessly restricts our theorizing, it undermines the empirical status of the representational theory of mind, and it encourages wildly deflationary and explanatorily vacuous conceptions of representation. After criticizing this outlook, I sketch alternative ways we might try to capture what is distinctive about cognition and cognitive theorizing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a dissenting voice, see Searle (1992).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. (2010). The language of thought hypothesis. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2010 edition). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/language-thought/.

  • Bechtel, W., & Mundale, J. (1999). Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states. Philosophy of Science, 66, 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamic systems perspective on agent–environment interaction. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 173–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. (2010). Cognitive science: An introduction to the science of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. New York: Kluwer/Springer Publishing.

  • Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2011). Radical, embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T., & Frankish, K. (2009). In two minds: Dual processes and beyond. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T. (2010). Thinking twice: Two minds in one brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankish, K. (2004). Mind and supermind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hull, C. L. (1930). Knowledge and purpose as habit mechanisms. Psychological Review, 37, 511–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2012). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco, CA: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. (1976). Computer science as empirical inquiry. Communications of the ACM, 19(3), 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cognitive Science, 4, 135–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119(1), 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P., & Legendre, G. (2006). The harmonic mind: From neural computation to optimality-theoretic grammar (Vol. 1), Cognitive architecture Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Stanovich, K., & West, R. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2014). Cognitive science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2014 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/cognitive-science/.

  • Thelan, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55, 189–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 91, 345–381.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Versions of this paper were presented at the “What is Cognition Conference?”, Center for Mind, Brain and Cognitive Evolution, Ruhr-Universität Bochum, Germany, June, 27–29, 2013; the “Reach of Radical Embodied Cognition Conference” University of Antwerp, Belgium, June 17–19, 2013; and the University of Milan, Italy, June 21, 2013. I am very grateful for helpful feedback from all of these audiences. I am also grateful to Ken Aizawa, Cameron Buckner, Ellen Fridland and two anonymous referees for extremely helpful suggestions and recommendations.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Ramsey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ramsey, W. Must cognition be representational?. Synthese 194, 4197–4214 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0644-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0644-6

Keywords

Navigation