Skip to main content

Cognitive Computation sans Representation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy and Computing

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 128))

Abstract

The Computational Theory of Mind (CTM) holds that cognitive processes are essentially computational, and hence computation provides the scientific key to explaining mentality. The Representational Theory of Mind (RTM) holds that representational content is the key feature in distinguishing mental from non-mental systems. I argue that there is a deep incompatibility between these two theoretical frameworks, and that the acceptance of CTM provides strong grounds for rejecting RTM. The focal point of the incompatibility is the fact that representational content is extrinsic to formal procedures as such, and the intended interpretation of syntax makes no difference to the execution of an algorithm. So the unique ‘content’ postulated by RTM is superfluous to the formal procedures of CTM. And once these procedures are implemented in a physical mechanism, it is exclusively the causal properties of the physical mechanism that are responsible for all aspects of the system’s behavior. So once again, postulated content is rendered superfluous. To the extent that semantic content may appear to play a role in behavior, it must be syntactically encoded within the system, and just as in a standard computational artifact, so too with the human mind/brain—it’s pure syntax all the way down to the level of physical implementation. Hence ‘content’ is at most a convenient meta-level gloss, projected from the outside by human theorists, which itself can play no role in cognitive processing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Brentano, F. (1874). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1996). Intelligence without representation. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind Design II. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). Language and nature. Mind, 104, 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1990). The language of thought: No syntax without semantics. Mind & Language, 5(3), 187–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewhurst, J. (2016). Individuation without representation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. (forthcoming in print). doi:10.1093/bjps/axw018.

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (1995). Computation and content. The Philosophical Review, 104, 181–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2010). Computational models: A modest role for content. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 253–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1981). The mind-body problem. Scientific American, 244, 124–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1994). The elm and the expert. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (2008). LOT 2 the language of thought revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milkowski, M. (2015). Satisfaction conditions in anticipatory mechanisms. Biology and Philosophy, 30, 709–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1986). Thoughts without laws; cognitive science with content. The Philosophical Review, 95(1), 47–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2006). Computation without representation. Philosophical Studies, 137, 205–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, M. (2014). The causal relevance of content to computation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88, 173–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, P. (2001). Realization, reduction and psychological autonomy. Synthese, 126, 383–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, P. (2009). The elimination of meaning in computational theories of mind. In A. Hieke & H. Leitgeb (Eds.), Reduction between the mind and the brain. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2001). Content, computation and externalism. Mind, 438, 369–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2014). The brain as a model of the world. Proceedings of the 50th Anniversary Convention of the AISB, Symposium on Computing and Philosophy. http://doc.gold.ac.uk.aisb50. Accessed 15 July 2015.

  • Shannon, C. E. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27(379–423), 623–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2010). Computation, individuation, and the received view on representations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 260–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the entscheidungsproblem. Proceeding of the London Mathematical Society, 42(series 2), 230–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1996). Dynamics and cognition. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind Design II. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank an anonymous IACAP reviewer for constructive comments, as well as Joe Dewhurst and Alistair Isaac for useful discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Schweizer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schweizer, P. (2017). Cognitive Computation sans Representation. In: Powers, T. (eds) Philosophy and Computing. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 128. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61043-6_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics