Skip to main content
Log in

La Meme Chose: How Mathematics Can Explain the Thinking of Children and the Thinking of Children Can Illuminate Mathematical Philosophy

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article offers a new interpretation of Piaget’s decanting experiments, employing the mathematical notion of equivalence instead of conservation. Some reference is made to Piaget’s theories and to his educational legacy, but the focus in on certain of the experiments. The key to the new analysis is the abstraction principle, which has been formally enunciated in mathematical philosophy but has universal application. It becomes necessary to identity fluid objects (both configured and unconfigured) and configured and unconfigured sets-of-objects. Issues emerge regarding the conflict between philosophic realism and anti-realism, including constructivism. Questions are asked concerning mathematics and mathematical philosophy, particularly over the nature of sets, the wisdom of the axiomatic method and aspects of the abstraction principle itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Birkhoff and MacLane (1965).

  2. I have discussed this a little further in Cable (2013).

  3. See, for example, Strawson and Chakrabarti (2006).

  4. As, for example, in Skemp (1971).

  5. Frege (1980/1884, §64).

  6. Einstein et al. (1923, p. 112).

  7. Bickhard (1997, p. 29).

  8. See Smith (1993, p. 35).

  9. See, for example, Devlin (1992).

  10. For example, Hale (2000) and Hale and Wright (2001).

  11. See, for example, Bennour and Vonèche (2009, p. 50).

  12. See, for example, Smith (1993).

References

  • Bennour, M., & Vonèche, J. (2009). The Historical Context of Piaget’s Ideas. In U. Muller, J. I. M. Carpendale, & L. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Piaget (pp. 45–63). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff, G., & MacLane, S. (1965). A survey of modern algebra (3rd ed.). New York: Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. (1997). Constructivisms and relativisms: A shopper’s guide. Science & Education, 6(1), 29–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cable, J. (2013). More equal than others. Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal, 27. http://people.exeter.ac.uk/PErnest/.

  • Cantor, G. (1996/1883). Foundations of a general theory of manifolds: A mathematico-philosophical investigation into the theory of the infinite. In W. Ewalt (Ed.), From Kant to Hilbert (Vol. 2, pp. 878–918). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Demetriou, A., Shayer, M., & Efklides, A. (1992). Neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development: implications and applications for education. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, K. (1992). The joy of sets (2nd ed.). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (2005/1954) Ideas and opinions. London: Souvenir Press.

  • Einstein, A., et al. (1923). The principle of relativity. London: Constable.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980/1884). The foundations of arithmetic (2nd revised ed.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Hale, B. (2000). Reals by abstraction. Philosophia Mathematica, 8(2), 100–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). The reason’s proper study: Essays towards a neo-Fregean philosophy of mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (Ed.). (1998). Constructivism in science education: A philosophical examination. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. (2003). Naked before reality; skinless before the absolute. Science & Education, 12(2), 131–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1961). The child’s conception of number. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., & Cook, M. (1955). The child’s construction of reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., & Szeminska, A. (1941). La Genese du Nombre chez l`Enfant. Neuchatel: Delachaus & Niestle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1994). Sense, nonsense, and the senses: an inquiry into the powers of the human mind. The Journal of Philosophy, 91(9), 445–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, J., & von Glasersfeld, E. (1980). Jean Piaget: psychologist of epistemology: A discussion of Rotman’s Jean Piaget: psychologist of the real. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 11(1), 29–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rotman, B. (1977). Jean Piaget: psychologist of the real. Hassocks: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucker, R. (1997/1982). Infinity and the mind: the science and philosophy of the infinite. London: Penguin.

  • Shayer, M., & Adey, P. (2002). Learning intelligence: Cognitive acceleration across the curriculum from 5 to 15 years. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skemp, R. R. (1971). The psychology of learning mathematics. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L. A. (1993). Necessary knowledge: Piagetian perspectives on constructivism. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F., & Chakrabarti, A. (2006). Universals, concepts, and qualities: new essays on the meaning of predicates. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld, E. (1995). Radical constructivism: a way of knowing and learning. London: Falmer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to acknowledge with thanks the help I have received in the preparation of this article from three reviewers of a previous version and from numerous members of the Mathematics Interest Group at Kings College London, especially Margaret Brown and Jeremy Hodgen.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Cable.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cable, J. La Meme Chose: How Mathematics Can Explain the Thinking of Children and the Thinking of Children Can Illuminate Mathematical Philosophy. Sci & Educ 23, 223–240 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9628-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9628-z

Keywords

Navigation