Skip to main content
Log in

Applicability, Indispensability, and Underdetermination: Puzzling Over Wigner’s ‘Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics’

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In his influential 1960 paper ‘The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences’, Eugene P. Wigner raises the question of why something that was developed without concern for empirical facts—mathematics—should turn out to be so powerful in explaining facts about the natural world. Recent philosophy of science has developed ‘Wigner’s puzzle’ in two different directions: First, in relation to the supposed indispensability of mathematical facts to particular scientific explanations and, secondly, in connection with the idea that aesthetic criteria track theoretical desiderata such as empirical success. An important aspect of Wigner’s article has, however, been overlooked in these debates: his worries about the underdetermination of physical theories by mathematical frameworks. The present paper argues that, by restoring this aspect of Wigner’s argument to its proper place, Wigner’s puzzle may become an instructive case study for the teaching of core issues in the philosophy of science and its history.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The indispensability thesis, promulgated by W.V.O. Quine and Hilary Putnam, is motivated by a realist commitment to those entities—including mathematical entities—that our best scientific theories quantify over.

  2. Interestingly, Baker (2005) only references Wigner’s 1960 paper indirectly, via (Schroeder 1992).

  3. While previous commentators on Wigner’s paper have noted that his ‘puzzle’ is really several problems rolled into one, they have tended to highlight the role of mathematics in the very discovery of scientific theories. Sometimes this departure from Wigner’s original concern is made explicit (e.g. by Steiner 1995, p. 153, fn. 68); sometimes it leads to a conflation of several distinct problems, as when Colyvan treats Steiner’s approach as a ‘version of Wigner’s thesis’ (Colyvan 2001, p. 267), thereby explicitly assimilating the two accounts into a single ‘Wigner/Steiner problem’ (ibid.).

  4. Feynman expresses a similarly optimistic view when he likens the multiplicity of mathematical approaches to ‘a bridge with lots of members, [which] is over-connected; if pieces have dropped out you can reconnect it another way’ (Feynman 1985: 47). (I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing me towards Feynman’s text; see also the discussion in Sect. 3 of this paper).

  5. One of the few exceptions is Wigner’s colleague and sometime co-author Henry Margenau, who seems to have Wigner’s underdetermination in mind when he insists that ‘historically, uniqueness of mathematical description certainly does not exist, and methodologically it is not necessary for the success of science’ (Margenau 1966, p. 354).

  6. This point has only recently started to receive attention; see (Gelfert 2011, esp. pp. 284–285) and references therein.

  7. What follows is only a rough sketch of structural realism and its relation to Wigner’s puzzle; a fuller discussion would require extensive engagement with the literature on structural realism, for which this is not the place.

  8. Ontic (as opposed to epistemic) structural realists go one step further in arguing that not only is structure all there is to know, but that structure is all there is. (For a review, including a discussion of structural realism’s historical influences, see Massimi 2010).

References

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuinely mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2009). Wigner’s puzzle for mathematical naturalism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 245–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrow, J. D. (1993). Pi in the sky: Counting, thinking and being. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The miracle of applied mathematics. Synthese, 127(3), 265–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2005). The flexibility of mathematics. In G. Boniolo, P. Budinich, & M. Trobok (Eds.), The role of mathematics in physical sciences: Interdisciplinary and philosophial aspects (pp. 115–129). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1985). The character of physical law. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2011). Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42(2), 272–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1992). Natur und mathematisches Erkennen: Vorlesungen, gehalten 19191920 in Göttingen. Ed. by D.E. Rowe. Basel: Birkhäuser.

  • Jones, R. (1991). Realism about what? Philosophy of Science, 58(2), 185–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29(3), 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malvern, D. (2000). Mathematical models in science. In J. K. Gilbert & C. J. Boulter (Eds.), Developing models in science education (pp. 59–90). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Margenau, H. (1966). Is the mathematical explanation of physical data unique? Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 44, 348–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M. (2010). Structural realism: A neo-Kantian perspective. In A. Bokulich & P. Bokulich (Eds.), Scientific structuralism (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 281; pp. 1–24). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • McAllister, J. W. (2005). Mathematical beauty and the evolution of the standards of mathematical proof. In M. Emmer (Ed.), The visual mind II (pp. 15–34). Cambridge (Mass.): The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (1992). The unreasonable effectiveness of number theory in physics, communication and music. In S. A. Burr (Ed.), The unreasonable effectiveness of number theory (pp. 1–20). Providence: American Mathematical Society.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1995). The applicabilities of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 3(2), 129–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, I. (2008). Why beauty is truth: A history of symmetry. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1993). Dreams of a final theory. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilholt, T. (2006). Lost on the way from Frege to Carnap: How the philosophy of science forgot the applicability problem. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 73, 69–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43(1–2), 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Sorin Bangu (Bergen), Grant Fisher (Daejeon), and Ricardo Karam (Hamburg) for comments on an earlier version of this paper, as well as to four anonymous reviewers for exceptionally detailed and helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Axel Gelfert.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gelfert, A. Applicability, Indispensability, and Underdetermination: Puzzling Over Wigner’s ‘Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics’. Sci & Educ 23, 997–1009 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9606-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9606-5

Keywords

Navigation