Skip to main content
Log in

Exemplarity in Mathematics Education: from a Romanticist Viewpoint to a Modern Hermeneutical One

Interpreting the Teaching of Infinitesimals as an Exemplary Theme

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper proposes a setting of exemplarity different from the already known one, which is basically a Romanticist philosophical setting. Our general aim is to describe and explore the nature of some exemplary themes and interpretive models in advanced mathematics teaching and learning. In order to do so, we move from Romanticism towards the viewpoint of Modern Hermeneutics, by applying ideas appearing mainly in Gadamer and Ricoeur. We use this new setting as a philosophical framework, to interpret some results from two didactical research studies that have already appeared on infinitesimals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hans-Georg Gadamer, a leading thinker in modern (philosophical) Hermeneutics, has considered interpretation and understanding of a text as an act of meeting and being confronted with something which is radically different from us but shares with us some common “ground”. This point of view questions objectification of meaning and seems to be particularly important in epistemology and pedagogy.

  2. This is e.g. the general view in the Bourbaki exposition of mathematics, in which interpretations are confined to the Notes Historiques at the end of each book of the Elements de Mathematique.

  3. This second characteristic was first suggested to us by Ricoeur’s own view of the character of Xerxes, in the tragedy Perses (Persians) of Aeschylus, as exemplary: Xerxes is accused as having provoked the Persians’ disaster but, at the same time, he is considered to be a victim of the Gods and therefore he is “an exemplary human person” who deserves the sympathy of the Athenian audience (Ricoeur 1988, p. 363).

  4. The following extract makes things clearer: “Leibniz postulated a system of numbers having the same properties as ordinary numbers but which included infinitesimals. …Yet Leibniz’ position seems absurd on its face. The ordinary real numbers obviously have at least one property not shared by Leibniz’ desired extension. Namely, in the real numbers, there are no infinitesimals. This paradox is avoided by specifying a formal language in the sense of modern logic (mercilessly precise in the same way that programming languages for computers are). Leibniz’ principle is then reinterpreted: there is an extension of the reals that includes infinitesimal elements and has the same properties as the real numbers insofar as those properties can be expressed in the specified formal language. One concludes that the property of being infinitesimal cannot be so expressed, or, as we shall learn to say: the set of infinitesimals is an external set.” (Davis 2005, p.2. Author’s emphasis).

  5. See note 4.

References

  • Arendt, H. (1991). Juger. Sur la philosophie politique de Kant. Paris: Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. L. (2005). The continuous and the infinitesimal in mathematics and philosophy. Milano: Polimetrica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beltrami, E. (1868a). Saggio di interpretrazione della geometria non-euclidea. Giornale di Mathematiche, 6, 284–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beltrami, E. (1868–69). Teoria fondamentale degli spazii di curvatura constante. Annali Di Mathematica Pura Et Applicata, 2(2), 232–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, T. (1991). Hermeneutics and mathematical activity. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 22, 475–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, T. (1994). Towards a hermeneutical understanding of mathematics and mathematical learning. In P. Ernest (Ed.), Constructing mathematical knowledge: Epistemology and mathematics education (pp. 141–150). London: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, T. (2001). Mathematics education and language interpreting: Interpreting hermeneutics and post-structuralism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. (2005). Applied nonstandard analysis. Mineola, NY: Dover publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1992). Hermeneutics and science education: an introduction. Science and Education, 1, 337–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1993a). Hermeneutics as an approach to science: Part I. Science and Education, 2, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1993b). Hermeneutics as an approach to science: Part II. Science and Education, 2, 303–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enriques, F., & Mazziotti, M. (1982). The theories of democritus from abdera. Xanthi: International Democritean Institution (in Greek).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischbein, E. (1987). Intuition in science and mathematics. An educational approach. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, G. (1981). The infinite and infinitesimal quantities of du Bois-Reymond and their reception. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 24(2), 101–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Ph. (1962). Philosophy of science. The link between science and philosophy. Mineola, NY: Dover Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. G. (1972). Hermeneutik als praktische Philosophie, In M. Riedel (Ed.), Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie, Band I., pp. 325–344.

  • Gadamer, H. G. (2002). The beginning of knowledge. New York–London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jahnke, H. N. (1989). Mathematics and systematic thinking: A historical note on an acute problem, In L. Bazzini & H. G. Steiner (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1st Italian–German bilateral symposium on didactics of mathematics, Pavia.

  • Jervolino, D. (1996). Gadamer and ricoeur on the hermeneutics of praxis. In R. Kearney (Ed.), Paul Ricoeur. The hermeneutics of action (pp. 63–79). London: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaisari, M., & Patronis, T. (2010). So we decide to call “straight line” (…): Mathematics students’ interaction and negotiation of meaning in constructing a model of elliptic geometry. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 75, 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khait, A. (2004). The definition of mathematics: Philosophical and pedagogical aspects. Science and Education, 14(2), 137–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1976). Proofs and refutations. The Logic of mathematical discovery. Cambridge: University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). Cauchy and the continuum: The significance of non-standard analysis for the history and philosophy of mathematics. In J. Worrall & G. Currie (Eds.), Mathematics, science and epistemology. Philosophical papers of Imre Lakatos (Vol. 2, pp. 43–60). Cambridge: University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1976). Knowledge and error. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (1989). The metaphysics of the calculus: A foundational debate in the Paris Academy of Science, 1700–1706. Historia Mathematica, 16(3), 224–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nikolantonakis, K. (2003). Pythagoras’ theorem: An example of proof from Euclid’s elements. In D. Chassapis (Ed.), Argument and proof in school mathematics (pp. 179–190). Thessaloniki: Aristotle University press (in Greek).

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2002). The world of parmenides: Essays for presocratic enlightenment. Athens: A. Kardamitsas (in Greek).

    Google Scholar 

  • Potaga, A. (2002). Mathematics: A compass into reality? Three alternatives. Athens: Nissos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981). ‘The model of the Text: Meaningful action considered as a text’, in: Paul Ricoeur hermeneutics and the human sciences. Essays on language, action and interpretation (pp. 204–206). Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1988). Finitude et culpabilite. Paris: Aubier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, A. M. (2003). Nonstandard analysis. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinet, A. (1968). Georges Lukacs. Paris: Seghers Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodin, A. (2006). Towards a hermeneutic categorical mathematics or why category theory goes beyond mathematical structuralism, http://arxiv.org/abs/math.GM/0608711.

  • Schiller, F. (1990). Letters on the aesthetic education of man. Athens: Odysseas (in Greek).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1996). The world as will and representation. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sierpinska, A. (1987). Humanities students and epistemological obstacles related to limits. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 18, 371–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skovsmose, O. (1994). Towards a philosophy of critical mathematics education. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spagnolo, F. (1995). Obstacles epistémologiques: Le postulat de Eudoxe-Archimède’, thèse de l’Université de Bordeaux I., Quaderni di Ricerca in Didactica, Supplemento al n.5, Palermo.

  • Spagnolo, F. (1999). Obstacles epistémologiques: Le postulat de Eudoxe-Archimède’. In Gagatsis (Ed.), A multidimensional approach to learning mathematics and science (pp. 123–162).Intercollege Press:Cyprus.

  • Stergiou, V. (2008). Historical evolution, interpretations and didactical approaches of the concept of infinitesimal, unpublished PhD Thesis, University of Patras, Department of Mathematics (in Greek).

  • Stergiou, V., & Patronis, T. (2002). Exploring a modern path to infinitesimals: Mathematics stydents’ understanding of the concept of rate of convergence. International Journal of Mathematical Education in Science and Technology, 33(5), 651–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toeplitz, O. (1963). The calculus: A genetic approach. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagenschein, M. (1965/1970). Ursprüngliches Verstehen und exaktes Denken I-II. Stuttgart:Ernst Klett Verlag.

  • Wagenschein, M. (1968). Verstehen das Lehren Genetisch-Sokratisch-Exemplarisch. Weinheim und Berlin: Verlag Julius Beltz.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dimitris Spanos.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Patronis, T., Spanos, D. Exemplarity in Mathematics Education: from a Romanticist Viewpoint to a Modern Hermeneutical One. Sci & Educ 22, 1993–2005 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9577-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-013-9577-6

Keywords

Navigation