Skip to main content
Log in

The Interplay of Scientific Activity, Worldviews and Value Outlooks

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scientific activity tends to reflect particular worldviews and their associated value outlooks; and scientific results sometimes have implications for worldviews and the presuppositions of value outlooks. Even so, scientific activity per se neither presupposes nor provides sound rational grounds to accept any worldview or value outlook. Moreover, in virtue of reflecting a suitable variety of worldviews and value outlooks, perhaps including some religious ones, science is better able to further its aim. An extended argument is made that, although the materialist worldview has de facto been widely associated with the development of modern science, the scope of scientific inquiry is improperly limited when constraints, derived from materialism, are generally placed upon admissible scientific theories. Some implications for science education are sketched in the conclusion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This statement of the aim of science draws upon arguments in Lacey (1999a, Ch. 5; 2004; 2005a, Part I). It is intended to be sufficiently encompassing to cover all the activities that scientists usually call “scientific,” and also controversially, not to exclude a priori from the category of “scientific” any forms of systematic empirical inquiry (including, e.g., those that generate the knowledge that informs traditional agricultural or medical practices). It also does not incorporate any metaphysical viewpoint. Obviously individual scientists and institutions may contest it, or they may articulate a variety of more specific aims, e.g., prioritizing differently the various components of the stated aim putting greater or less emphasis on understanding or utility, or subordinating it to other interests (personal, military, corporate or financial) of their own. Furthermore, philosophers may interpret the aim according to favored epistemological or metaphysical viewpoints, e.g., empiricist or realist (van Fraassen 1980).

  2. Worldviews may be more or less articulated. A largely unarticulated worldview may form part of the taken-for-granted “common sense” of a culture, making it resistant to critical appraisal and development through participation in rational dialogue. However, any worldview can develop. Just as “scientific” worldviews develop over time (largely in response to scientific developments), although a considerable body of scientists always tends to lag behind, so too “religious” worldviews can develop (also, in part, in response to scientific developments). Criticism of worldviews should be attentive to these matters.

  3. For details and defense of the account of values sketched here, see Lacey (1999a, Ch. 2; supplemented by 2005a, Sects. 1.1, 3.1). It is illustrated below (Sect. 3) when presuppositions of the values of technological progress are introduced.

  4. In the cited works I called these “materialist strategies.” Here I refer to them as “strategies that fit into DA” (see criticism offered by McMullin 1999, to Lacey 1999b).

  5. See also Porpora (2006) for arguments about limitations of “methodological agnosticism” for investigating religious experience.

  6. Dennett has an interesting response, in which he proposes a pragmatic role for “intentional stance,” which he distinguishes from the “design” and the “physical” stances, and which may be applied (he maintains) not only to human agents, but also to numerous material systems such as computers and robots (Dennett 1987).

  7. I have been bemused by generations of my students treating materialism as if it were given a priori, arguing that the categories it favors uniquely meet appropriate standards of intelligibility, even as they un-self-consciously display clarity as they fluently use intentional idiom in making their arguments.

  8. If materialism is a presupposition of scientific activity then, without further ado, viewpoints like creationism and “intelligent design” are “non-” or “anti-scientific.” But why is it legitimate to constrain permissible theories to accordance with materialism, and not to accordance with these viewpoints? The real problem for the scientific status of these outlooks is that they do not engender fruitful research strategies, i.e., strategies that enable theories to be accepted and knowledge confirmed according to standard scientific canons of appraisal—and, in the case of creationism, that it makes claims that are inconsistent with well-confirmed scientific results.

  9. This is not to say that scientific research per se aims immediately for application; that all confirmed scientific results do lead to applications (understanding need not be systematically subordinated to utility); that adopting DA is always rationalized by reference to these relations with VTP (see Sect. 4.4); or that all results consolidated within DA fail to serve interests of value outlooks that contest VTP. I do contend, however, that, where VTP is contested, granting exclusivity to DA is also challenged; and also that, generally, choice of research strategy should be responsive to the general features of the objects of investigation, rather than our conception of such features being subordinated to what can be grasped under a favored strategy (see Sect. 3.4, Thesis, 4).

  10. Variations on such proposals are integral to the rhetoric of advocating that public support be made available for technoscientific advances. We find them in advertisements, news programs, editorial comments, political campaign rhetoric, and in the statements of spokespersons of scientific institutions when they seek funds for their on-going projects: e.g., stem-cell research, the human genome project, nanotechnology, and research and development of transgenics. More and subtle social scientific research on these matters would be welcome. See Lacey (2005a, part II) for documentation of the rhetoric in the transgenics case (see also Note 16), and also for all other matters in the text referring to transgenics and to forms of agriculture that do not use them, especially agroecology.

  11. See Lacey (2005a, Ch. 11; 2006a: Ch. 6) for how proposals like (d) may be investigated empirically.

  12. I do not question the epistemic credentials of results properly accepted within DA. I do question, however, that their epistemic credentials suffice to endorse their general social value compared to the value of the other results, which have comparable epistemic credentials, that I maintain may be obtained under alternative strategies that do not fit into DA. (The epistemic credentials of the science—conducted according to DA—that has led to developments of transgenics are not superior to those of the science—conducted under strategies that are not reducible to those that fit into DA—that informs agroecology; and, for certain value outlooks, the latter has greater social value; see Sect. 4.2)

  13. Knowledge confirmed within DA is cognitively neutral, i.e., it has no logical implications in the domain of values, since the categories of its theories lack value categories. This does not mean that it manifests applied neutrality, i.e., that it may inform more or less evenhandedly projects that embody any viable value outlook (Lacey 1999a, Ch. 10). In the text I am referring to applied neutrality.

  14. How the analysis of the transgenics case can be generalized to many other (though not all) technoscientific innovations warrants further discussion. Note that those who hold VSGE do not deny the value of technological innovation per se. Rather they appraise the value of technological innovations case-by-case in the light of how they may fit into the projects that embody these values. VSGE and VTP cannot be pursued simultaneously in the same social locations, for their respective pursuits require incompatible conditions.

  15. For details on agroecological strategies see Lacey (2005a, Sect. 5.4), and for documentation of the empirical fruitfulness of research conducted under them see Altieri (1995) and Lacey (2005a, Ch. 10). Note that agroecological strategies complement DA and often make use of results consolidated within it; knowing the chemical and microorganism components of agroecological systems, e.g., depends on research conducted within DA. No one recommends that research conducted within DA be altogether dropped and replaced by agroecological research, but only that it cease to be privileged to the point of exclusivity. DA does retain a measure of privilege: all strategies can make use of some results obtained within it, and so it is an essential and major component of scientific research per se.

  16. It was not foreseen (at least, not well publicized) that the implementations of the Green Revolution would risk considerable environmental degradation and that its crops would become highly vulnerable to infestations. Now, it is said, introducing certain varieties of transgenics can contribute to reverse these damages: the “solution” to damage caused by technoscientific implementations is more, and more sophisticated, technoscience. Also recently, following the publication of the international report on the fact of global warming and its causal roots in aspects of industrial and technological practices, there has been a veritable avalanche of newspaper articles, reflecting presupposition (b) and also (c), advocating technoscientific solutions to the problem (e.g., Tierney 2007).

  17. Holding VSGE has presuppositions, including the qualified negation of those of VTP, that are open to empirical inquiry. That there can be a religious ground (among others) for striving to bring about alternatives for the future is empirically relevant to appraising, e.g., presupposition (iv) of VTP. However, consistency with the worldview of liberation theology is not a criterion for appraising either the scientific credentials of results generated under agroecological strategies or the presuppositions of VSGE.

References

  • Altieri MA (1987) Agroecology: the scientific basis of alternative agricultures. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Altieri MA (1995) Agroecology: the science of sustainable agriculture, 2nd edn. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Altieri MA, Yurjevic A, Von der Weid JM, Sanchez J (1996) Applying agroecology to improve peasant farming systems in Latin America. In: Costanza R, Segura O, Martinez-Alier J (eds) Getting down to earth: practical applications of ecological economics. Island Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer M, Collier A, Porpora D (2004) Transcendence, critical realism and god. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (1968) A materialist theory of the mind. Routledge & K. Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland P (1999) Eliminative materialism. In: Perry J, Bratman M (eds) Introduction to philosophy: classical and contemporary readings. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier A (2003) On christian belief. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • COMEST – World Commission on the Ethics of Science, Technology (2005) The precautionary principle. UNESCO, Paris

  • Cottingham J (2005) The spiritual dimension: religion, philosophy and human value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (2006) The god delusion. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (2006) Breaking the spell: religion as a natural phenomenon. Viking, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Donagan A (1987) Choice: the essential element in human action. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas H (2000) Inductive risk and values in science. Philos Sci 67:559–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1993) The disorder of things: metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei G (1623) The assayer. In: Discoveries and opinions of Galileo, translated with an introduction and notes by Stillman Drake, Garden City, NJ, Doubleday, 1957

  • Gauch HG (2007) Science, worldviews and education. Sci & Educ. doi:10.1007/s11191-006-9059-1

  • Lacey H (1999a) Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (1999b) Scientific understanding and the control of nature. Sci & Educ 8(1):13–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (2004) Is there a significant distinction between cognitive and social values? In: Machamer P, Wolters G (eds) Science, values and objectivity. Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh, pp 24–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (2005a) Values and objectivity in science. Lexington, Lanham, MD

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (2005b) On the interplay of the cognitive and the social in scientific practices. Philos Sci 72(5):977–988

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (2006a) A Controvérsia sobre os Transgênicos: Questões Científicas e Éticas. Idéias e Letras, São Paulo

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H (2006b) O Princípio de Precaução e a Autonomia da Ciência. Sci Stud 4(3):373–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey H, Schwartz B (1996) The formation and transformation of values. In: O’Donohue W, Kitchener R (eds) The philosophy of psychology. Sage, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner M, Bunge M (1996) Is religious education compatible with science education? Sci & Educ 5(2):101–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mariconda P, Lacey H (2001) A Águia e os Estorninhos: Galileu sobre a Autonomia da Ciência. Tempo Social 13:49–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell N (2004) Is science neurotic? Imperial College Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (1999) Materialist strategies. Sci & Educ 8(1):37–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overbye D (2007) Free will: now you have it, now you don’t. The New York Times, 2 January 2007, F1, 4

  • Porpora D (2006) Methodological atheism, methodological agnosticism and religious experience. J Theory Social Behav 36:57–76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin H (1994) Behavior and mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver LM (2006) Challenging nature: the clash of science and spirituality at the new frontiers of life. HarperCollins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (1985) Human agency and language: philosophical papers, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor C (2002) Varieties of religious experience: varieties of religion today. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney J (2007) An early environmentalist embracing new ‘Heresies’. The New York Times, 27 February 2007, F1, 3

  • van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (2002) The empirical stance. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hugh Lacey.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lacey, H. The Interplay of Scientific Activity, Worldviews and Value Outlooks. Sci & Educ 18, 839–860 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9114-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9114-6

Keywords

Navigation