Skip to main content
Log in

Measuring Loss Aversion under Ambiguity: A Method to Make Prospect Theory Completely Observable

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We propose a simple, parameter-free method that, for the first time, makes it possible to completely observe Tversky and Kahneman’s (1992) prospect theory. While methods exist to measure event weighting and the utility for gains and losses separately, there was no method to measure loss aversion under ambiguity. Our method allows this and thereby it can measure prospect theory’s entire utility function. Consequently, we can properly identify properties of utility and perform new tests of prospect theory. We implemented our method in an experiment and obtained support for prospect theory. Utility was concave for gains and convex for losses and there was substantial loss aversion. Both utility and loss aversion were the same for risk and ambiguity, as assumed by prospect theory, and sign-comonotonic trade-off consistency, the central condition of prospect theory, held.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This extension requires finding events with decision weight ½, which can be complex.

  2. Throughout this paper we use the term prospect theory for the 1992 version of the theory and the term original prospect theory (OPT) for the 1979 version. Because we only consider two-outcome prospects, OPT is the special case of prospect theory for decision under risk in which probability weighting for gains and losses are the same.

  3. For example, Choquet expected utility (Schmeidler 1989), maxmin expected utility (Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989), α-maxmin expected utility (Ghirardato et al. 2004), and contraction expected utility (Gajdos et al. 2008).

  4. For example, original prospect theory (Kahneman and Tversky 1979), rank-dependent expected utility (Quiggin 1981; Quiggin 1982), prospective reference theory (Viscusi 1989), and disappointment aversion theory (Gul 1991).

  5. Booij and van de Kuilen (2009) investigated the robustness of their findings by using probability weights estimated in other studies.

  6. Again, we may select an event \( E^{{\prime\prime} } \) different from the events employed in the other two stages.

  7. Köbberling and Wakker (2003) define sign-comonotonic trade-off consistency formally. In a nutshell, the condition holds because changing from -€300 into €0 does not change the rank-ordering and the sign (no loss is turned into a gain or vice versa) of each prospect’s payoffs. Then utility differences should not be affected according to prospect theory.

  8. Three subjects (two for risk and one for ambiguity) violated monotonicity so that \( {x}_6^{-} \) was not the largest loss. For these subjects we transformed losses \( {x}_j^{-} \) to \( {x}_j^{-}/\left\{\underset{i=1,\dots, 6}{ \min }{x}_i^{-}\right\} \).

  9. These computations required that \( -{x}_j^{+} \) was contained in [\( {x}_6^{-},0) \) and \( -{x}_j^{-} \) in (\( 0,{x}_6^{+}]. \)

  10. We use the (standard) nomenclature of Landis and Koch (1977) to describe the strength of associations.

  11. For a given j, \( {x}_j^{+} \) and \( {x}_j^{-} \) have the same absolute value of utility by construction, \( U\left({x}_j^{+}\right)=-U\left({x}_j^{-}\right), \) and, thus, \( {x}_j^{+}>-{x}_j^{-} \) implies that \( U\left({x}_j^{+}\right)<-U\left(-{x}_j^{+}\right) \), consistent with Kahneman and Tversky’s definition of loss aversion (U(x) <   – U(– x) for all x > 0).

  12. Bleichrodt et al. (2010) also concluded that error propagation was negligible in their measurements using the trade-off method.

  13. We assumed that the error terms followed an AR(1) process ϵ t  + ρϵ t - 1 = u t  with u t normally distributed with expectation 0 and variance σ 2 and estimated this using generalized least squares.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M. (2000). Parameter-free elicitation of utility and probability weighting functions. Management Science, 46, 1497–1512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Baillon, A., Placido, L., & Wakker, P. P. (2011). The rich domain of uncertainty: Source functions and their experimental implementation. American Economic Review, 101, 695–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., & Paraschiv, C. (2007). Measuring loss aversion under prospect theory: A parameter-free approach. Management Science, 53, 1659–1674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., Vossmann, F., & Weber, M. (2005). Choice-based elicitation and decomposition of decision weights for gains and losses under uncertainty. Management Science, 51, 1384–1399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baltussen, G., Van den Assem, M., & Van Dolder, D. (forthcoming). Risky choice in the limelight. Review of Economics and Statistics.

  • Barberis, N. C. (2013). Thirty years of prospect theory in economics: A review and assessment. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 27, 173–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bardsley, N., Cubitt, R., Loomes, G., Moffatt, P., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (2010). Experimental economics: Rethinking the rules. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, M. H., & Bahra, J. P. (2007). Gain-loss separability and coalescing in risky decision making. Management Science, 53, 1016–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., & Pinto, J. L. (2000). A parameter-free elicitation of the probability weighting function in medical decision analysis. Management Science, 46, 1485–1496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Cillo, A., & Diecidue, E. (2010). A quantitative measurement of regret theory. Management Science, 56, 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Booij, A. S., & van de Kuilen, G. (2009). A parameter-free analysis of the utility of money for the general population under prospect theory. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30, 651–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Booij, A. S., van Praag, B. M. S., & van de Kuilen, G. (2010). A parametric analysis of prospect theory’s functionals for the general population. Theory and Decision, 68, 115–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bostic, R., Herrnstein, R. J., & Luce, R. D. (1990). The effect on the preference reversal of using choice indifferences. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 13, 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowman, D., Minehart, D., & Rabin, M. (1999). Loss aversion in a consumption-savings model. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 38, 155–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruhin, A., Fehr-Duda, H., & Epper, T. (2010). Risk and rationality: Uncovering heterogeneity in probability distortion. Econometrica, 78, 1372–1412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C. R., & Poldrack, R. A. (2014). Prospect theory and the brain. In P. Glimcher, & E. Fehr (Eds.), Handbook of Neuroeconomics (2nd ed.) (pp. 533–567). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gaechter, S., Johnson, E. J., & Herrmann, A. (2007). Individual-level loss aversion in risky and riskless choice. IZA Discussion Paper No. 2961.

  • Gajdos, T., Hayashi, T., Tallon, J. M., & Vergnaud, J. C. (2008). Attitude toward imprecise information. Journal of Economic Theory, 140, 27–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P. & M. Marinacci (2001). Ambiguity Made Precise: A Comparative Foundation, Journal of Economic Theory, 102, 251–289

  • Ghirardato, P., Maccheroni, F., & Marinacci, M. (2004). Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. Journal of Economic Theory, 118, 133–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F. (1991). A theory of disappointment aversion. Econometrica, 59, 667–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling, V., & Wakker, P. P. (2003). Preference foundations for nonexpected utility: A generalized and simplified technique. Mathematics of Operations Research, 28, 395–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köbberling, V., & Wakker, P. P. (2005). An index of loss aversion. Journal of Economic Theory, 122, 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2006). A model of reference-dependent preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121, 1133–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landis, J. R., & Koch, G. G. (1977). The measurement of observer agreement for categorical data. Biometrics, 159–174.

  • Luce, R. D (1991). Rank- and sign-dependent linear utility models for binary gambles. Journal of Economic Theory, 53, 75–100.

  • Luce, R. D. (2000). Utility of gains and losses: Measurement-theoretical and experimental approaches. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neilson, W. S. (2002). Comparative risk sensitivity with reference-dependent preferences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24, 131–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennings, J. M. E., & Smidts, A. (2003). The shape of utility functions and organizational behavior. Management Science, 49, 1251–1263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulford, B. D. (2009). Is luck on my side? Optimism, pessimism, and ambiguity aversion. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62, 1079–1087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1981). Risk perception and risk aversion among Australian farmers. Australian Journal of Agricultural Economics, 25, 160–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2000). Risk aversion and expected-utility theory: A calibration theorem. Econometrica, 68, 1281–1292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stott, H. P. (2006). Cumulative prospect theory's functional menagerie. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 32, 101–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2003). Reference-dependent subjective expected utility. Journal of Economic Theory, 111, 172–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vieider, F. M., Cingl, L., Martinsson, P., & Stojic, H. (2013). Separating attitudes towards money from attitudes towards probabilities: Stake effects and ambiguity as a test for prospect theory. WZB Berlin: Working Paper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K. (1989). Prospective reference theory: Toward an explanation of the paradoxes. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W. K., & Magat, W. A. (1992). Bayesian decisions with ambiguous belief aversion. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 371–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P. (2010). Prospect theory: For risk and ambiguity. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P., & Deneffe, D. (1996). Eliciting von Neumann-Morgenstern utilities when probabilities are distorted or unknown. Management Science, 42, 1131–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. P., & Tversky, A. (1993). An axiomatization of cumulative prospect theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 7, 147–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, G., & Markle, A. B. (2008). An empirical test of gain-loss separability in prospect theory. Management Science, 54, 1322–1335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We gratefully acknowledge helpful comments from Aurélien Baillon, Ferdinand Vieider, Peter P. Wakker, Horst Zank, and an anonymous reviewer and financial support from the Erasmus Research Institute of Management, the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO), the Tinbergen Institute, Rennes Metropole district (AIS_2013), and the Economic and Social Research Council via the Network for Integrated Behavioral Sciences (award n. ES/K002201/1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mohammed Abdellaoui.

Appendix

Appendix

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., L’Haridon, O. et al. Measuring Loss Aversion under Ambiguity: A Method to Make Prospect Theory Completely Observable. J Risk Uncertain 52, 1–20 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-016-9234-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-016-9234-y

JEL Classifications

Keywords

Navigation