1 Introduction and overview

According to the basic (“procedural”) norm of Buchanan’s andTullock’s seminal Calculus of Consent, (1962/1999, vol. 3),Footnote 1 any substantive normative content can become valid law provided that the “democratic sovereign” (“could conceivably have”) accepted it with “democratic unanimity in the shadow of individual veto power”. That any content can become law if it is identified as law by a factually prevailing “rule of recognition” (Hart, 1961) is the central legal positivist tenet while the normative proviso of “democratic unanimity in the shadow of individual veto power” goes beyond a positivist rule of recognition in that it rules out content and is in this sense functionally equivalent to substantive normative requirements of natural law theories.Footnote 2

In what follows I shall, first, identify in Buchanan’s approach to constitutional law mirror images of crucial elements of Hans Kelsen’s “pure theory of law” (see Sect. 2).Footnote 3 Next, I will sketch why Buchanan must fail in aligning his own broadly Hartian positivism and ethical relativism with his conception of the authority of constitutional democratic procedures (see Sect. 3). As a final observation I will indicate why I regard Buchanan’s as a variant of philosophical contractarianism that is superior to most of its competitors but also why I remain ultimately unconvinced by contractarianism (see Sect. 4). – Since Buchanan typically launches his own theoretical assaults on foundational issues from Hobbesian ideas let me start from there, too.Footnote 4

2 From Hobbes to Buchanan

Hobbes characterized the "state of nature" by the absence of obligations to commit or to omit any act.Footnote 5 Since for him all obligations concerning overt action are „artificially “ created through factual conventions (positive social rules and positive law) nothing is ruled out as normatively illegitimate a priori.

2.1 Hobbesian natural law

Hobbes refers to the absence of all “positive” obligations in state of nature as the „natural right” to everything. Since there are no (positive) obligations corresponding to it this „right to everything “ bestows no (institutional) legal powers on actors.Footnote 6 In line with this in Leviathan the term „law of nature “ refers to technological recipes (advice) of how to get one’s way in pursuit of contingently “given” ends. These recipes are expressive of empirical knowledge to the extent that the achievement of given aims, ends or values can be furthered by bringing about the antecedent conditions of the underlying factual law-like regularities.Footnote 7

Restricting the powers of reason to instrumental rationality Buchanan accepts that reason cannot tell us which substantive ends should be pursued.Footnote 8 Accusing those who claim objective knowledge of ends to “play at being God” (Buchanan, 1975/2000, p. 4)Footnote 9 he insists that the democratic body politic is endowed with the ultimate normative authority to set ends and to enact rules in fundamental constitutional politics.Footnote 10 Having ultimate authority the community of all members of a polity is substantively unconstrained while procedurally constrained by the unanimity proviso.Footnote 11

According to the preceding reconstruction, the “democratic body politic” of the calculus is sovereign in the classical Hobbesian sense of commanding an externally unconstrained monopoly to create valid law. Whatever comes out of the democratic procedure of unanimous collective choice making on the foundational constitutional stage is—independently of its substantive normative content—to be treated as legitimate law and only that. Contrary to this view, for typical „natural law “ approaches content that violates certain substantive natural law demands cannot be rendered law—not even by the unanimous agreement of all.Footnote 12 When Buchanan rejects the latter view this is in the spirit of Hartian legal positivism which insists on the conceptual distinction between law that is from law as ought to be.Footnote 13 At the same time Buchanan and Tullock, in the spirit of natural law theory, seek to restrict the power to enact law procedurally on the ultimate constitutional level by the “internal” requirement of “unanimous agreement of all in the shadow of universal veto power”:

In discussing an original constitution or improvements in an existing constitution, we shall adopt conceptual unanimity as a criterion … First, only by this procedure can we avoid making interpersonal comparisons among separate individuals. Secondly, in discussing decision rules, we get into the familiar infinite regress if we adopt particular rules for adopting rules. To avoid this, we turn to the unanimity rule, since it is clear that if all members of a social group desire something done that is within their power, action will be taken regardless of the decision rule in operation. (1962/1999, vol. 3, p.15).

That unanimity concerning content is to be regarded as sufficient for bestowing the status of positive law on the basic constitution seems plausible. However, the tenet that content can become positive law only if the conceptual unanimity proviso is fulfilled, is highly implausible—in particular on the sub-constitutional level. In view of this Buchanan and Tullock allow on the constitutional level for what Hart called power conferring rules that delegate legal powers to citizens, the legislature and courts. Yet, the scope and limits of this practically necessary delegation must be interpreted with care, since

it is precisely at this level that profound and ultimately dangerous confusion emerges about the role of the state in making constitutional law and in modifying the whole set of legal arrangements, including the assignment of individuals’ rights and claims. In its most blatant form this confusion emerges in the form of legal positivism, which states that ‘the law’ is what the state determines it to be and that individual rights are, and must be defined, by the state and, as a consequence are necessarily dependent on the state. (Buchanan, 2001a, vol.18, p. 176)Footnote 14

In the spirit of the Anglo Saxon rule of law tradition all legal powers— including those of a sub-constitutional state legislature—are to be conceived as bound by constitutional law. In Buchanan’s account this constitutional law is positive law whose substantive content is acknowledged to be agreement- rather than knowledge-based.Footnote 15 As a criterion of validity a constitution that meets the test of “conceptual unanimity among all parties in the political group” (Buchanan & Tullock, 1962/1999, vol. 3, p.7) is meant to serve the same functions as knowledge of what the law “ought to be” in natural law theories.Footnote 16

2.2 Unanimity as basic democratic requirement

Buchanan’s foundational principle of collective choice making under the unanimity constraint fulfills functions of Kelsen’s (basic norm) „ Grundnorm “. Since “ought cannot be derived from is”, a Grundnorm, thinks Kelsen must be (“hypothetically”) presupposed for identifying valid law and what ought to be done according to it. Moreover, the hierarchical structure of the legal order („Stufenbau der Rechtsordnung”) renders normative legal validity hereditary (or a matter of pedigree). This bestows unity on the legal order and provides criteria of what is and what is not part of it.Footnote 17

Like Kelsen’s basic norm Buchanan’s democratic unanimity provides a—substantively unconstrained—„formal “ foundation of legal validity and unity of the legal order by „authorizing “ all rules as originating from a single constitutional procedure as its unique source. Buchanan is aware that not all law is enacted law. In his (as in Kelsen’s) account other sources can be authorized to create valid law. Yet, both Buchanan and Kelsen believe a. that for the sake of determinateness of law there must be single ultimate criterion for what is and what is not part of a legal order and b. that the criterion cannot be merely descriptively identifying what is a legal norm.

To the extent that democratic bodies did not impose substantive restrictions on the powers they transferred to courts the latter may decide without any substantive restrictions.Footnote 18 However, to the extent that the power conferring rules are determinate in not conferring certain powers the courts have no law-making authority at all. For Buchanan, courts are bound to play by the “law as is” and according to the power conferring and restraining rules that the law that is, as a matter of fact provides.Footnote 19

If courts do not follow a mode of interpretation in which finding has priority over making law the authority of the basic procedure and the control that the sovereign exerts over the constitution are undermined. The determinateness of law which is necessary to allow for definite commitments and compromises on the level of rule choice becomes endangered (a much-neglected effect of the ever-present proclivity to interpret law “creatively” in the name of “ethics” and other considerations deemed “higher” than the constitution).Footnote 20

The structural similarities between Kelsen’s and Buchanan’s basic conceptions include some of the more precarious aspects of Kelsen’s legal positivism, as well. In particular, Kelsen thought of the Grundnorm as a quasi-transcendental „pre-supposition“ necessary to constitute law as an object of his „pure“ theory of law. Similarly, Buchanan conceives of conceptual unanimity as ultimately unavoidable assumption (a „relatively absolute absolute “) of a theory of legitimate order in a constitutional democracy.

To accept the authority of factually prevailing unanimity as sufficient for fixing legitimate law seems indeed a kind of unavoidable consequence of our modern understanding of respect for individual and collective/democratic autonomy. It is from a modern point of view hard to imagine what could meaningfully be objected against real agreement of virtually all individuals (including unanimous agreement to commit suicide). However, whether or not rules could “conceivably” be the (direct) result of unanimity, can hardly be decisive for the factual status of law: If the constitutional rules that do not meet the test of conceptual unanimity do not automatically lose their factual influence on the real world—which, to put it euphemistically, is empirically unlikely—it becomes unclear what the criterion of conceptual (fictitious) unanimity says about the factual status of those rules as “positive” constitutional law.

The question looms large why real people who as a matter of fact have not agreed should care about what all would conceivably have agreed to under some ideal—contrary to fact—conditions. From a philosophical point of view unsurprisingly, in his efforts to justify the relevance of such merely conceivable conditions and uses of his basic procedural norm Buchanan becomes a kind of Kantian, a “Bukantian”.Footnote 21

3 Bukantianism

The requirement of “unanimous agreement in the shadow of universal individual veto power” is normative and—in that sense—reaches beyond “the logical [emphasis added, HK] foundations of constitutional democracy” (Buchanan & Tullock, 1962/1999, vol. 3, subtitle). It is instructive to take a closer look at Buchanan’s efforts to argue for “conceptual unanimity” as a “relatively absolute absolute” with reasons that do not appeal only to him personally.Footnote 22

3.1 Unanimity as expressive of political Kantianism

Where Kant uses an ideal “form “ of imperatives and “conceivable universalizability” of “maxims of the will“ Buchanan introduces an ideal “procedure“ and requires conceptual unanimity or unanimous agreement under it as a test. The Kantian abstract principle of inter-personal respect of neverFootnote 23 intentionally using another person only as “a means to an end“Footnote 24 is expressed in procedural terms by the veto condition; that is, to the extent that all affected individuals could have used their—collectively guaranteed—veto but omitted to make use of it none can have been used „only as means“.

Kant’s practical philosophy was strongly influenced by his intense reading of Rousseau. In response, Kant seeks to resolve the tension between Rousseau’s “general will” and the prevailing “will of all” by testing the maxim of the individual will for its universalizability. What can conceivably be a universal law for all individuals who are endowed with reason cannot use others as mere instruments.Footnote 25

The basic procedure underlying the “foundations of constitutional democracy” provides also a solution for the eternal conflict between individual self-determination and collective co-determination. Rousseau states the problem thus:

‘The problem is to find a form of association which will defend and protect with the whole common force the person and goods of each associate, and in which each, while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as before.’ This is the fundamental problem of which the Social Contract provides the solution. ((Rousseau, 1762/1923), chap VI, „The social compact”.)

Buchanan’s solution of “unanimous agreement of all in the shadow of universal veto power” starts from collective rather than individual decision making on all matters while building Kantian interpersonal respect into the constitutional procedure itself. From a philosophical point of view this way of reducing the ideal theory of constitutional democracy to its core principle must be counted among the greater—if widely unnoticed—analytical accomplishments of modern political philosophy. For philosophers who focus on ideal theory standards in evaluating real world institutions of “liberal democracies” it can serve as a guiding principle when developing an evaluative metric.Footnote 26

Yet, Buchanan intends to justify his solution with arguments that do not transcend the limits of economic instrumental rationality. Then—if reason is restricted to instrumental rationality—problems arise from the fact that the universality of Buchanan’s solution depends on normative premises that are not universally but only contingently fulfilled: the solution presupposes that (a.) the community of individuals is exogenously “given” and (b.) has a monopoly on all legitimate choices. If (a.) were not fulfilled, then who has a vote (“voice”) and would be respected by the community through granting her or him a veto might not include all members of the relevant “demos”. If (b.) were not fulfilled, then there could exist dimensions along which individuals would not be guaranteed a veto by the community and therefore could be used by it as means to its ends.Footnote 27

The (“ultimate”) collective monopoly on all legitimate choice making in a pre-defined community along with the universal individual veto assures that neither the collectivity as a whole nor any of its members (no member is entitled to act on her own) can ever act in a way that uses a member of the community only as a means.Footnote 28 Buchanan unites the Weberian state monopoly of the use of violence with the Kantian restriction of that political monopoly to what respects the autonomy of each and every member of the body politic.Footnote 29

As indicated already, if real consent ever would fulfill the demanding conditions of Buchanan’s basic norm of “democratic unanimity in the shadow of universal individual veto power” this would be the end of the argument. In this sense Buchanan succeeds as an ideal theory philosopher in establishing the ideal. Yet, since real unanimity will as a matter of fact never be forthcoming Buchanan has to invoke not only real but also merely conceptual unanimity if he wants to say something about non-ideal states of the world. He has to come up with an argument why his fiction is relevant for real actors. Again he does so in a philosophically interesting way but on that way violates the self-imposed “legal positivist and ethical relativist” constraints.

3.2 Conceptual unanimity – Bukantianism’s clay feet

Even if those gathered around the philosophical campfire or at the „round table of deliberative democracy “ (or whatever is the philosophical fashion of the day) may in fact all concur in their discussion that agreement is conceivable, the conceivability claim itself remains a mere theoretical („logical “) conclusion and not the consent itself. The conception is not its (“conceived”) object (as an image is not the object it represents). That real people are used as „mere means “ in real politics is not prevented by imagining that they would assent to what happens to them under ideal (i.e. non-real) conditions.

Moreover, if A has apples a and B has bananas b, A prefers having b to having a and B prefers having a to having b, then it can be predicted that presumably A and B would agree that a and b switch places. Yet the prediction that this would happen is not the agreement to swap a with b. Neither is it an exchange if somebody else, say, C would switch the places of a and b since it would make both better off without the agreement of A and B.

To prevent using real persons as means they must actually be asked. The conceivability of agreement generates merely the empirical hypothesis that they might agree. It has none of the normative ethical force that we commonsensically and legally ascribe to real agreement and the “volenti non fit iniuria” responsibility ascription that supports it.Footnote 30

Buchanan himself acknowledges this in his central programmatic paper „What should economists do? “ (1999a, vol.1). There he insists that economists should restrict themselves to identifying possible Pareto improvements. Only if the proposals they make are universally advantageous can agreement-seeking political economists as participants of political interaction hope to find among the rational actors whom they address universal agreement (rather than merely universal advantage as diagnosed from an objective point of view).Footnote 31 Even if the suggestions of constitutional political economy are to the mutual advantage of all members of the community this is in the eyes of Buchanan not sufficient to justify implementation of the suggestions. To legitimately implement them, all suggestions have to be ratified by agreement.Footnote 32

Buchanan’s precedingly sketched justification of what constitutional economists should do is a fine piece of integrated practical ethics. It coherently combines demands on participants of the practices of constitutional democracy with demands on participants of constitutional economics within a constitutional democracy. Yet, whatever such coherent constitutional economics proposes it cannot be expected that its own criteria of legitimate implementation be actually fulfilled.Footnote 33 Real unanimous agreement in a Great Society does not exist.Footnote 34 Neither is there real universal agreement that fictitious, merely conceivable agreement should be used as a relevant criterion. Moreover, if we take the Kantianism in Buchanan’s “pure theory of constitutional democracy” as seriously as the emphasis on universal veto-power suggests, approximations in terms of supermajority requirements below unanimity will not do.

As a final line of defense, it might be pointed out that in a Great Society no theory whatsoever will generate real unanimous approval of its proposals. If no theory can generate real unanimous agreement, we might as well assess theories according to their comparative merits along other dimensions, or so the argument might run. Yet, precisely because Buchanan-type constitutional economics is honestly contractarian and therefore takes agreement (other than e.g. Rawls’ merely metaphorical contractarianism with its focus on mutual advantageFootnote 35) as foundational category seriously, Buchanan-type constitutional economics cannot take this way out.

4 Conclusion

For Buchanan the basic constitutional conventions of constitutional democracy derive legitimacy from the authority of agreement rather than the authority of knowledge. To keep fully in line with this in his normative theory he would have to restrain himself to proposing a procedure compliant with democratic unanimity in the shadow of universal individual veto power that he would expect to be self-referentially accepted in real universal agreement. The “rest” would be “over to the citizens” whose real agreement to and under the constraints of the basic procedure would legitimize specific constitutional conventions as positive law. As an economic theorist Buchanan would have to remain silent on the content of such agreement-based constitutional law. Yet, Buchanan wants to go beyond the procedural proposal and to say something as a constitutional economic theorist about substantive constitutional rules.Footnote 36

For this he brings in the fiction of conceptual unanimity rather than real unanimity. That all sorts of fictions have had high currency in economics—in particular in general equilibrium analysis and game equilibrium models—is perhaps an excuse but no justification for relying on fictions in constitutional economics.

In response Buchanan could have taken openly to philosophical methods of justification and could have relied on a search for Rawlsian reflective equilibrium. Within such a philosophical enterprise “unanimous agreement in a democratic community” could have served as a characterization of a “democratic original position” in which representative rational choice makers act as avatars of the citizens. As in the extended Rawlsian search for reflective equilibrium in his Theory of Justice (1971) this could have been embedded into an account of the factually prevailing practices of Western Great Societies and the basic intuitions of citizens concerning how specific problems should be solved according to the practices in which they do as a matter of historical fact participate. Buchanan’s communitarian contractarian construction could then have been based on a democratic original position embodied in real political practices and opinions to fully show its metal as the important contribution to twentieth century political philosophy that it without doubt is.Footnote 37

The empirical hypothesis that complicated narratives are potentially doing more harm than good when it comes to stabilizing Great Societies is all but outlandish, though.Footnote 38 For instance, the description of something as if it were the outcome of universal agreement makes it look more harmless than it is. As a matter of fact, it is imposed on individuals. The application of fundamental coercion is merely camouflaged. Describing it as if of the agreement type makes it as a matter of fact harder to distinguish between acceptable and non-acceptable coercion.

In view of such real risks the nicest thing that can safely be said about ideal theory approaches of theoretical economics, practical philosophy etc. might well be that they are practically impotent. In the latter case we could enjoy intoxication by beautiful constructions without any hangover at the horizon. However, thinking of the Keynesian scribblers (among which today Keynes himself would have to be counted), we must be aware that theoretical fictions of the past can influence present opinion and often for worse rather than better. Since it is “on opinion only that government is founded” (Hume, 1985, 32), I tend to believe that it may be better to restrict the authority of constitutional political economy to the role of witnessing facts including those that are relevant to opinion formation.

For such and some more theoretical reasons at least I remain skeptical that engaging elaborate philosophical theories will do much good.Footnote 39 In the end empirical Public Choice theory without the normative underpinnings of normative constitutional political economy will presumably serve technological purposes of economic constitutional policy analysis best. In particular the purpose of finding means towards the end of protecting liberty and its priority in a constitutional democracy may be served better by an empirical understanding of how constitutional democracies actually work than by any contractarian fictions. Still, since political reflection as a matter of fact will not stop as long as constitutional democracies exist we can as well enjoy Buchanan’s fascinating theories beyond his 100th anniversary and hope, as he certainly did, that this will make the world a better place by shaping our opinions in ways supporting the rule of law.