Skip to main content
Log in

Can a contractarian be a paternalist? The logic of James M. Buchanan’s system

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

At various points in his work, James Buchanan mentions favorably the idea of private constitutional choice, that is, it can be rational for a present-biased individual to constrain her future behavior by self-imposed rules of personal conduct. Given that in a classical liberal world such self-constitutions would face no political or legal obstacle, we ask whether reasonable people would call on the state to assist them in the enforcement of their personal constitutions. In this paper, we provide several arguments for the incompatibility of Buchanan’s contractarianism with various forms of state paternalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A variation of the definition given by Dworkin (2002) in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition).

  2. Typically, behavioral welfare economics rests on the assumption that it is possible to classify particular types of choices as “decision mistakes”. Those are “decisions that [individuals] would not have made if they had paid full attention and possessed complete information, unlimited cognitive abilities, and complete self-control” (Thaler and Sunstein 2008, p. 5). It is assumed that decision mistakes drive a wedge between an agent’s choice and her underlying “true” or “intrinsic” preferences. In order to reconstruct the subset of “true” preferences, behavioral welfarists take preference consistency as the normative criterion for welfare-increasing choice (Berg and Gigerenzer 2010). In doing so, that “preference purification” approach rests on the assumption that each person has a rational agent with well-defined preferences deep within herself that is struggling to surface because she is impaired by psychological biases that trigger systematic judgment mistakes (Whitman and Rizzo 2015).

  3. If the optimum is not unique, then an array of resource allocations will be available and an array of rules will be possible at the self-constitutional stage.

  4. On Stickk.com users sign up to ‘commitment contracts’ in which they set their own goals at the outset, e.g., losing x pounds of weight or exercising y days per week. Users agree to donate a certain amount of money to friends or a charity of their choice if they fail to reach their goals.

  5. For an in-depth discussion of Buchanan’s normative starting point, see Dold (2018a).

  6. Hyperopia means farsightedness. In the context of choice, it means that individuals weigh future benefits more heavily than present ones, i.e., other things equal, hyperopic agents prefer the more distant of two equally large payoffs (Loewenstein 1987).

  7. More technically, it is a recursive decision process. The individual predicts how his future selves will interpret a present decision not to apply the rule. Suppose that he predicts that they will interpret it as a violation or defection, then in recursive fashion the present self will incorporate that prediction into his present decision. Similarly, all of the n future selves will assume that the just prior (n − 1) self also will defect when it becomes a present self. As a result, the prospect of future benefits owing to self-constraining behavior is lost.

  8. On the implications of Buchanan’s subjectivism for “true preference” paternalism, see Dold and Rizzo (2020, forthcoming) and Dold (2018b).

  9. The simple, unbiased presentation of information about the options that individuals face in the case of complex choices is not at issue here. We are focusing on the ascertainment of “true” preferences. We do not consider the provision of information to be paternalistic since it does not direct the individual toward any particular decision (Hertwig and Grüne-Yanoff 2017). Rational individuals behind the veil could assign that task to government.

  10. The payoffs in the matrix can be understood as numerical representations of the preferences of the two selves.

References

  • Ainslie, G. (2012). Pure hyperbolic discount curves predict “eyes open” self-control. Theory and Decision,73(1), 3–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, N., & Gigerenzer, G. (2010). As-if behavioral economics: Neoclassical economics in disguise? History of Economic Ideas,18, 133–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D., & Rangel, A. (2007). Behavioral public economics: Welfare and policy analysis with non-standard decision makers. In P. Diamond & H. Vartiainen (Eds.), Economic institutions and behavioral economics (pp. 7–77). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., & Buchanan, J. M. (1985). The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1976). The justice of natural liberty. The Journal of Legal Studies,5(1), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1979[1999]). Natural and artifactual man. In The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Vol. 1: The logical foundations of constitutional liberty (pp. 246–259). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1984). Rights, efficiency, and exchange: The irrelevance of transaction costs. Ansprüche, Eigentum und Verfügungsrechte (pp. 9–24). Berlin: Duncker and Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1986). Liberty, market, and state. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1987). The constitution of economic policy. The American Economic Review,77(3), 243–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1991a). The contractarian logic of classical liberalism. In The economics and ethics of constitutional order (pp. 125–35). Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1991b). The foundations of normative individualism. In The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Vol. 1: The logical foundations of constitutional liberty (pp. 281–291). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, Inc.

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2005a). Afraid to be free: Dependency as desideratum. Public Choice,124, 19–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (2005b). Why I, too, am not a conservative: The normative vision of classical liberalism. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J., & Congleton, R. (1998). Politics by principle, not interest: Toward nondiscriminatory democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dold, M. (2018a). A Smithian critique of James M. Buchanan’s constitutional contractarianism. In D. Boudreaux, C. Coyne, & B. Herzberg (Eds.), Interdisciplinary studies of the market order: The political process and political order (pp. 17–40). Rowman and Littlefield International Ltd: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dold, M. (2018b). Back to Buchanan? Explorations of welfare and subjectivism in behavioral economics. Journal of Economic Methodology,25(2), 160–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dold, M., & Rizzo, M. (2020, forthcoming). Old Chicago against static welfare economics. Journal of Legal Studies.

  • Dworkin, G. (2002). Paternalism. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/paternalism/.

  • Hertwig, R., & Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017). Nudging and boosting: Steering or empowering good decisions. Perspectives on Psychological Science,12(6), 973–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, F. H. (1935). Intellectual confusion on morals and economics. The International Journal of Ethics,45(2), 200–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Grand, J., & New, B. (2015). Government paternalism: Nanny state or helpful friend?. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (1987). Anticipation and the valuation of delayed consumption. The Economic Journal,97(387), 666–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, M. J., & Arnold, F. S. (1980). Causal apportionment in the law of torts: An economic theory. Columbia Law Review,80(7), 1399–1429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, M. J., & Whitman, G. (2020). Escaping paternalism: Rationality, behavioral economics and public policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2018). The community of advantage: A behavioural economist’s defence of the market. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R., & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V., & Buchanan, J. M. (1989). Interests and theories in constitutional choice. Journal of Theoretical Politics,1(1), 49–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, G. (2006). Against the new paternalism: Internalities and the economics of self-control. In Policy Analysis, 563, 1–16, Washington DC: Cato Institute.

  • Whitman, D. G., & Rizzo, M. J. (2015). The problematic welfare standards of behavioral paternalism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology,6(3), 409–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to express their gratitude to Robert Sugden for providing helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Malte F. Dold.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rizzo, M.J., Dold, M.F. Can a contractarian be a paternalist? The logic of James M. Buchanan’s system. Public Choice 183, 495–507 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-020-00804-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-020-00804-7

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation