Skip to main content
Log in

The Problematic Welfare Standards of Behavioral Paternalism

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Behavioral paternalism raises deep concerns that do not arise in traditional welfare economics. These concerns stem from behavioral paternalism’s acceptance of the defining axioms of neoclassical rationality for normative purposes, despite having rejected them as positive descriptions of reality. We argue (1) that behavioral paternalists have indeed accepted neoclassical rationality axioms as a welfare standard; (2) that economists historically adopted these axioms not for their normative plausibility, but for their usefulness in formal and theoretical modeling; (3) that broadly rational individuals might fail to satisfy the axioms for various reasons, making them unpersuasive as normative criteria; and (4) that even if their violation did constitute irrationality, that would not justify paternalists’ choosing among inconsistent preferences to define an individual’s “true” preferences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “The hypothesis of rationality is embodied in two basic assumptions about the preference relation…: completeness and transitivity.” Mas-Colell et al. (1995: 6).

  2. See, for instance, Gintis (2009). Gintis’s definition of completeness has the preference relation defined with respect to specific choice sets, so that A might be preferred to B for one choice set and B to A for another. Then he introduces IIA as a third axiom, and notes: “Because of the third property [IIA], we need not specify the choice set and can simply write [that A is preferred to B]” (5, bracketed changes made for consistency of notation).

  3. Or by reflexivity, which is sometimes regarded as a separate axiom. But usually, reflexivity is taken to be implied by the definitions of indifference and strict preference in terms of weak preference: If A is weakly preferred to B and vice versa, then A ~ B; if A is weakly preferred to B but not vice versa, then A is strictly preferred to B. By these definitions, it’s simply impossible to have A strictly preferred to A.

  4. See, for instance, Sunstein and Thaler (2003: 1168): “Of course, rational people care about the taste of food, not simply about health, and we do not claim that everyone who is overweight is necessarily failing to act rationally.” Sunstein (2014: 75): “… I am interested in defending paternalists who respect choosers’ own views about their ends, and who seek to increase the likelihood that their decisions will promote those ends.” Sunstein (2014: 96): “With respect to diet, savings, exercise, romance, credit cards, mortgages, cell phones, health care, computers, and much more, different people have divergent tastes and situations, and they balance the relevant values in different ways.”

  5. The view that behavioral models are positive while neoclassical models are normative was common in the early days of behavioral economics. Floris Heukelom observes, “Contrary to [Herbert] Simon, [Daniel] Kahneman and [Amos] Tversky argued that there was nothing wrong with economists’ theory of expected utility maximization. It was only that this was the normative theory, and not an accurate description of actually observed human behavior” (2014: 127).

  6. There is an unfortunate ambiguity in the word “normative” when referring to rules. There are constitutive rules and regulative or prescriptive rules (Searle 1969). The rules of chess may be likened to constitutive rules. They define what it means to be playing chess. Violate them sufficiently and you are not playing chess. The rules of safe driving are prescriptive rules. Violate them and you are still driving but not safely. The axioms of rationality are constitutive rules. If you obey them you are a “rational” agent in the sense of standard economic theory. Whether you should be such an agent in particular circumstances is a separate matter that needs to be argued for explicitly.

  7. Sugden (2004: 1028–9) offers a related but distinct response to the money-pump argument: that competition among potential money-pumpers keeps profits to a minimum, thereby making money pumps ineffective at extracting value from consumers in equilibrium – even if such consumers have incoherent preferences.

  8. For further discussion see Anand (1993).

  9. For a discussion of the general concept of rationality and the reasonableness test, see Rescher (1988).

  10. See Schnellenbach (2012) for more on the knowledge problem as applied to time-discounting.

  11. Rizzo and Whitman (2009: 925): “We could just as easily designate the more near-sighted preferences as the correct ones, and then aim to make far-term choices better correspond to them.”

  12. See Rizzo and Whitman (2009: 929–931).

  13. See Rizzo and Whitman (2009: 929).

  14. See Rizzo and Whitman (2009. 904–905).

  15. See Rizzo and Whitman (2009, 930).

  16. This is explicitly stated by Bernheim and Rangel (2007: 16): “We assume that people attempt to optimize given their true preferences, but randomly encounter conditions that trigger systematic mistakes…”

References

  • Anand, P. 1993. The philosophy of intransitive preference. The Economic Journal 103: 337–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J. 1959. Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica, New Series 26(102): 121–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. 2012 [1951]. Social choice and individual values. New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Arrow, K.J., and G. Debreu. 1954. Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica 22(3): 265–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, N., and G. Gigerenzer. 2010. As-if behavioral economics: Neoclassical economics in disguise? History of Economic Ideas 18(1): 133–165.

  • Bernheim, B.D., and A. Rangel. 2007. Behavioral public economics: Welfare and policy analysis with non-standard decision makers. In Behavioral economics and its applications, ed. P. Diamond and H. Vartiainen, 7–84. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M. 1979. Natural and artifactual man. In What should economists do? ed. J.M. Buchanan, 93–112. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1982). Order defined in the process of its emergence. Reader’s forum on Norman Barry’s “The tradition of spontaneous order,” The forum at the online library of liberty, available at http://www.econlib.org/library/Essays/LtrLbrty/bryRF1.html.

  • Camerer, C., S. Issacharoff, G. Loewenstein, T. O’Donoghue, and M. Rabin. 2003. Regulation for conservatives: Behavioral economics and the case for “Asymmetric Paternalism”. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151(3): 1211–1254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conly, S. 2012. Against autonomy: Justifying coercive paternalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T. 1991. Self-constraint versus self-liberation. Ethics 10(2): 360–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. 1954. Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In Decision processes, ed. R.M. Thrall, C.H. Coombs, and R.L. Davis, 159–165. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S., G. Loewenstein, and T. O’Donoghue. 2002. Time discounting and time preference: A critical review. Journal of Economic Literature 40(2): 351–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J., and B. Koszegi. 2001. Is addiction “Rational”? Theory and evidence. Quarterly Journal of Economics 116(4): 1261–1303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. 2002. Competition as a discovery procedure. Quarterly Journal of Economics 5(3): 9–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heukelom, F. 2014. Behavioral Economics: A History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Jolls, C., and C.R. Sunstein. 2006. Debiasing through law. The Journal of Legal Studies 35(1): 199–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., J.L. Knetsch, and R.H. Thaler. 1991. Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives 5(1): 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. 2000. Emotions in economic theory and economic behavior. American Economic Review 90(2): 426–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., and M. Mariotti. 2009. Choice over time. In The handbook of rational and social choice: An overview of new foundations and applications, ed. P. Anand and P.K. Pattanaik, 239–270. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A., M.D. Whinston, and J.R. Green. 1995. Microeconomic theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., and M. Rabin. 2003. Studying optimal paternalism, illustrated by a model of sin taxes. American Economic Review 93(2): 186–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., and M. Rabin. 2006. Optimal sin taxes. Journal of Public Economics 90(10–11): 1825–1849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redelmeier, D.A., P. Rozin, and D. Kahneman. 1993. Understanding patients’ decisions: Cognitive and emotional perspectives. Journal of the American Medical Association 270(1): 72–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1988. Rationality: A philosophical inquiry into the nature and the rationale of reason. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo, M.J., and D.G. Whitman. 2009. The knowledge problem of new paternalism. Brigham Young University Law Review 2009(4): 905–968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnellenbach, J. 2012. Nudges and norms: On the political economy of soft paternalism. European Journal of Political Economy 28(2): 266–277.

  • Searle, J.R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. 2004. The opportunity criterion: Consumer sovereignty withou the assumption of coherent preferences. The American Economic Review 94(4): 1014–1033.

  • Sunstein, C.R. 2014. Why nudge? New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C.R., and R.H. Thaler. 2003. Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. University of Chicago Law Review 70(4): 1159–1202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R.H. 1991. Quasi rational economics. New York: Russell Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R.H., and C.R. Sunstein. 2003. Libertarian paternalism. American Economic Review 93(2): 175–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R.H., and C.R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzawa, H. 1956. Note on preference and axioms of choice. Annals of the Institute of Statistical Mathematics 8: 35–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ware, B. 2012. The top five regrets of the dying: A life transformed by the dearly departing. Carlsbad: Hay House.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas Glen Whitman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Whitman, D.G., Rizzo, M.J. The Problematic Welfare Standards of Behavioral Paternalism. Rev.Phil.Psych. 6, 409–425 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0244-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0244-5

Keywords

Navigation