Skip to main content
Log in

Quantum gravity, timelessness, and the contents of thought

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A number of recent theories of quantum gravity lack a one-dimensional structure of ordered temporal instants. Instead, according to many of these views, our world is either best represented as a single three-dimensional object, or as a configuration space composed of such three-dimensional objects, none of which bear temporal relations to one another. Such theories will be empirically self-refuting unless they can accommodate the existence of conscious beings capable of representation. For if representation itself is impossible in a timeless world, then no being in such a world could entertain the thought that a timeless theory is true, let alone believe such a theory or rationally believe it. This paper investigates the options for understanding representation in a three-dimensional, timeless, world. Ultimately it concludes that the only viable option is one according to which representation is taken to be deeply non-naturalistic. Ironically then we are left with two seemingly very unattractive options. Either a very naturalistic motivation—taking seriously a live view in fundamental physics—leads us to a very non-naturalistic view of the mental, or else views in the philosophy of mind partly dictate what is an acceptable theory in physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more on various kinds of temporal error theory see Baron and Miller (2015) and Tallant (2008).

  2. For a related discussion of self-falsifying propositions see Bardon (2005).

  3. It suffices to either think of theories as models (which represent, or fail to represent, the way the world is) or as sets of propositions (which jointly represent, or fail to represent, the way the world is). Then the wordily state represented by an entertaining of, say, a timeless theory, is the worldly state that the theory qua model, models, or the worldly state that the set of propositions represent. Believing the theory to be true, then, is believing that the model holds of the world, or believing that the set of propositions are jointly true.

  4. In particular, we do not mean by ‘representation’ the relatively specific doctrine called the ‘Representational Theory of the Mind’ by Fodor and others, which requires belief in very local and syntactically individuable representational states, and is more or less equivalent to the Language of Thought hypothesis.

  5. Points, here, are points in configuration space; they are not point-sized objects: each is a three-dimensional object.

  6. There is no reason to suppose that this phrase denotes the essentially modal notion that the phrase has in the lexicon of most philosophers.

  7. Though we do not require that perdurantism is true: arguably one can make sense of there existing a lonely intrinsic duplicate of an enduring object at-a-time.

  8. See Harman (1982); for a more skeptical take see Lepore (1994).

  9. See for instance Dowe (1992).

  10. Such as, for instance Lewis (1973).

  11. It is of the first importance to avoid big, widespread, diverse violations of law.

    It is of the second importance to maximize the spatiotemporal region throughout which perfect match of particular fact prevails.

    It is of the third importance to avoid even small, localized, simple violations of law.

    It is of little or no importance to secure approximate similarity of particular fact, even in matters that concern us greatly (Lewis 1979, p. 472).

  12. This may not pick out a single unique path. Baron and Miller suggest that this will make little difference to the evaluation of counterfactuals.

  13. For a useful survey of such views see Cummins (1989).

  14. Exactly what naturalism is, and how to characterize it, is a vexed issue. If naturalism is nothing more than following science where it takes us, then perhaps almost all defenders of timeless theories are motivated by naturalism. Equally, there are other characterizations of naturalism that build more into a conception of naturalism, and which might be such that at least some defenders of timeless theories are not motivated by naturalism thus understood.

References

  • Anderson, E. (2006). Relational particle models: 1. Reconciliation with standard classical and quantum theory. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 23(7), 2469–2490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2009). Records theory. International Journal of Modern Physics D, 18(4), 635–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2012a). Problem of time in quantum gravity. Annalen der Physik, 524(12), 757–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2012b). The problem of time in quantum gravity. In V. R. Frignanni (Ed.), Classical and quantum gravity: Theory, analysis and applications (pp. 1–25). New York: Nova.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. (1994a). The timelessness of quantum gravity: I. The evidence from the classical theory. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 11(12), 2853–2873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. (1994b). The timelessness of quantum gravity: II. The appearance of dynamics in static configurations. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 11(12), 2875–2897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. (1999). The end of time. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardon, A. (2005). Performative transcendental arguments. Philosophica, 33(1–4), 69–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2014). Causation in a timeless world. Synthese, 191(12), 2867–2886. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0427-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S., & Miller, K. (2015). What is temporal error theory? Philosophical Studies, 172(9), 2427–2444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J., & Isham, C. (1999). On the emergence of time in quantum gravity. In J. Butterfield (Ed.), The arguments of time (pp. 111–168). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, D. (1997). The fabric of reality: The science of parallel universes and its implications. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodd, P. J., & Halliwell, J. J. (2003). Decoherence and records for the case of a scattering environment. Physical Review D, 67(10), 105018. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.67.105018

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (1992). Wesley Salmon’s process theory of causality and the conserved quantity theory. Philosophy of Science, 59, 195–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1983). Precis of knowledge and the flow of information. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 55–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1977). Logic, meaning and conceptual role. Journal of Philosophy, 69, 379–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gell-Mann, M., & Hartle, J. B. (1994). Time symmetry and asymmetry in quantum mechanics and quantum cosmology. In J. Halliwell, J. Perez-Mercader, & W. Zurek (Eds.), Physical origins of time asymmetry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1982). Conceptual role semantics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 23, 242–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2002). Can physics coherently deny the reality of time? In C. Callender (Ed.), Time, reality and experience (pp. 293–316). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (2005). Reflections on meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E. (1994). Conceptual role semantics. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. (1994). Content: Covariation, control and contingency. Synthese, 100, 241–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989a). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56(2), 288–302, and reprinted in Millikan, 1993(a) op. cit.

  • Millikan, R. (1989b). Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy, 86, 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1995). Malfunctioning and misrepresenting. Philosophical Studies, 79, 109–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1996). Swampman meets swampcow. Mind and Language, 11(1), 70–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H (2008). Two notions of naturalism. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4430/1/Tilburg1.pdf. Retrieved November 2017.

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956). The direction of time. Berkeley: University of Los Angeles Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. (1995). Analysis of the distinct meanings of the notion of time in different physical theories. Il Nuovo Cimento, 110 B(1), 81–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. (2004). Quantum gravity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. (2007). The disappearance of space and time. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 25–36). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D. (1986). Verification and a causal account of meaning. Synthese, 69, 107–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallant, J. (2008). What is it to “B” a relation? Synthese, 162, 117–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Jonathan Tallant, Oliver Pooley, Carlo Rovelli, Jeremy Butterfield, Sam Baron and Adrian Bardon, and participants at the International Association or the philosophy of Time Association (2016) for helpful criticisms and encouragement. The study was funded by Australian Research Council with Grant Nos. DP110100486, FT170100262, DP11010048.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristie Miller.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Braddon-Mitchell, D., Miller, K. Quantum gravity, timelessness, and the contents of thought. Philos Stud 176, 1807–1829 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1097-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1097-4

Keywords

Navigation