Skip to main content
Log in

Minimizing indexicality

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I critically examine Cappelen and Lepore’s definition of and tests for indexicality, and refine them to improve their adequacy. Indexicals cannot be defined as expressions with different referents in different contexts unless linguistic meaning and circumstances of evaluation are held constant. I show that despite Cappelen and Lepore’s claim that there are only a handful of indexical expressions, their “basic set” includes a number of large and open classes, and generates an infinity of indexical phrases. And while the tests can be used effectively to combat contextualism concerning ‘knows’ and ‘actual,’ many expressions not in their basic set test positive for indexicality, including quantifier nouns, weather reports, and comparative adjectives. I rebut their claim that context-shifting arguments inevitably lead to radical contextualism, and that if there were any indexicals beyond their basic set, communication would be impossible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for example Travis (1996, p. 454; 1997, p. 87), Recanati (2004, pp. 4, 56–58, 96–97, 136, 153, 154; 2005, pp. 174, 188). Searle (1980) was a forerunner.

  2. I presented prior drafts of this paper to the Arché Group at the University of St. Andrews in April 2008 and in the July 2011 “Content, Context and Conversation” workshop hosted by the Lichtenberg-Kolleg in Göttingen. I’m especially grateful to Herman Cappelen, Jonathan Schaffer, Jeff King, Nick Asher, Christian Beyer and anonymous referees for their comments.

  3. See e.g., Bar-Hillel (1954, p. 359), Montague (1968, p. 103), Lewis (1970, p. 184ff), Stalnaker (1976, p. 229), Lyons (1977, pp. 106, 637, 646), Leezenberg (1994, p. 1648), Perry (1997, p. 586), Levinson (2003), and Braun (2007).

  4. MacFarlane (2009) argues that the standard definition is too broad for different reasons, maintaining that extension can vary with context of use without content varying. I dispute this in Davis (2012, 2013b).

  5. Cf. Husserl (1900, 1.1.26, 6.1.5), Gale (1967, p. 151), Smith (1989), Plumer (1993).

  6. See Davis (2003, pp. 250–254).

  7. For non-deictic uses of ‘I’ and ‘now,’ see Davis (2011, 2013a, forthcoming: §v) and below. In Davis (2013a) I sketch a positive characterization of the deictic use as that in which the speaker’s perceptual or introspective focus determines the referent in a particular way, a theory I develop at length in Indexical Meaning and Concepts.

  8. I develop such a theory in Indexical Meaning and Concepts.

  9. Cappelen and Lepore call this the “collective description” test. I presume the test is whether it follows that ‘A and B both v’ is true not that is ever uttered.

  10. This is the basis of the identity test for ambiguity. See Zwicky and Sadock (1975).

  11. See also Cappelen and Hawthorne (2009, p. 34).

  12. Cappelen and Lepore (2005a, pp. 1–2) use ‘disquotational’ for such reports.

  13. When a pronoun is used anaphorically, its referent is (or is related to) that of its antecedent. In the most natural interpretation of (5), the antecedent of ‘he’ in both uses is ‘the composer of Fidelio.’ But in other contexts of use, ‘he’ can be used demonstratively in (5) (imagine Ann and Bob pointing at a picture of Mozart), or deictically (imagine a context in which Ann and Bob are focused on the most perceptually salient male). In non-anaphoric uses, ‘he’ would naturally be emphasized. So indexicals not only have different referents in different contexts, the determinants of their referents vary depending on whether they are used anaphorically, demonstratively, or deictically.

  14. Cf. Humberstone (2006, pp. 312–315), Hawthorne (2006, p. 445), Cappelen and Hawthorne (2009, pp. 40–42).

  15. Cf. Williamson (2005, pp. 215–217). Cappelen and Lepore (2005a, p. 105) look at whether there are or can be false utterances of ‘p’ even though p.

  16. See Davis (forthcoming).

  17. Cf. Williamson (2005, p. 224). Compare and contrast Hawthorne (2004, pp. 100–101) and DeRose (2009, pp. 172–173).

  18. Cf. Borg (2007, §iii), Pagin and Pelletier (2007, p. 53).

  19. Cappelen and Lepore (2005a, p. 39; 2006, pp. 430, 470–471).

  20. See Doerge (2010) for a discussion of incompleteness arguments.

  21. It is also necessary to know in both cases how specific a location the speaker has in mind. Ann could in both cases be describing the weather in Brittany, or more specifically in Brest, or more specifically still in her neighborhood in Brest.

  22. Cf. Hawthorne (2006, p. 448), Borg (2007, §iii), Pagin and Pelletier (2007, p. 53).

  23. This is MacFarlane’s (2005a, b) tack. Bach (2006) proposes instead that ‘It is cloudy’ expresses a propositional radical, and that only its completions have truth values.

References

  • Bach, K. (2006). The excluded middle: Semantic minimalism without minimal propositions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 435–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1954). Indexical expressions. Mind, 63, 359–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2007). Minimalism vs. contextualism in semantics. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism: New essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 339–360). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2007). Indexicals. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (pp. 1–33). Stanford, CA. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/indexicals/.

  • Cappelen, H., & Hawthorne, J. (2009). Relativism and monadic truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005a). Insensitive semantics: A defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005b). A tall tale: In defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism: New essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 197–220). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2006). Précis of insensitive semantics and replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 425–434, 469–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2007). Knowledge claims and context: Loose use. Philosophical Studies, 132(3), 395–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2011). Indexicals. In P. C. Hogan (Ed.), The Cambridge encyclopedia of the language sciences (pp. 382–383). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2012). Context-sensitivity without indexicality? In C. Jäger & W. Löffler (Eds.), Epistemology: Contexts, values, disagreement, Proceedings of the 34th International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium (pp. 41–52). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2013a). Indexicals and de se attitudes. In A. Capone & N. Feit (Eds.), Attitudes ‘de Se’: Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics (pp. 29–58). Palo Alto, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2013b). On nonindexical contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 163, 561–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (forthcoming). The semantics of actuality terms: Indexical vs. descriptive theories. Noús.

  • Davis, W. A. (manuscript). Indexical meaning and concepts: Pronouns and beyond.

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doerge, F. C. (2010). The collapse of insensitive semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 33, 117–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale, R. M. (1967). Indexical signs, egocentric particulars, and token-reflexive words. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. 4, pp. 151–154). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2006). Testing for context-sensitivity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73, 443–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (2006). Sufficiency and excess. Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volume, 80, 265–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1900). Logical investigations (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). New York: Humanities Press (1970).

  • Jespersen, O. (1922). Language: Its nature, development, and origin. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leezenberg, M. (1994). Indexicals. In R. Asher (Ed.), Encyclopedia of language and linguistics (pp. 1648–1651). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2003). Deixis. In W. J. Frawley (Ed.), International encyclopedia of linguistics (Vol. 2, pp. 423–424). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). Anselm and actuality. Noús, 4, 175–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005a). The assessment sensitivity of knowledge attributions. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 1, pp. 197–233). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2005b). Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 105, 321–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2009). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166, 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1968). Pragmatics. In R. Klibansky (Ed.), Contemporary philosophy (pp. 102–122). Florence: La Nuova Italie Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P., & Pelletier, F. J. (2007). Content, context, and compositions. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism: New essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 25–62). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1997). Indexicals and demonstratives. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 586–612). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plumer, G. (1993). A here-now theory of indexicality. Journal of Philosophical Research, 18, 193–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2005). Literalism and contextualism: Some varieties. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism: New essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 171–196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). The background of meaning. In J. Searle, F. Kiefer, & M. Bierwisch (Eds.), Speech act theory and pragmatics (pp. 221–232). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Q. (1989). The multiple uses of indexicals. Synthese, 78, 167–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1976) Possible worlds. Noús, 10, 65–75. (Reprinted in The possible and the actual, pp. 225–234, by M. J. Loux, Ed., 1979, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (1995). Quantifiers and context-dependence. Analysis, 55, 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (1996). Meaning’s role in truth. Mind, 100, 451–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (1997). Pragmatics. In B. Hale & C. Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 87–107). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2005). Contextualism, subject-sensitive invariantism, and knowledge of knowledge. Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 213–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky, A. M., & Sadock, J. (1975). Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In J. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 4 (pp. 1–36). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne A. Davis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Davis, W.A. Minimizing indexicality. Philos Stud 168, 1–20 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0191-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0191-x

Keywords

Navigation