Skip to main content
Log in

Knowledge claims and context: loose use

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is abundant evidence of contextual variation in the use of “S knows p.” Contextualist theories explain this variation in terms of semantic hypotheses that refer to standards of justification determined by “practical” features of either the subject’s context (Hawthorne & Stanley) or the ascriber’s context (Lewis, Cohen, & DeRose). There is extensive linguistic counterevidence to both forms. I maintain that the contextual variation of knowledge claims is better explained by common pragmatic factors. I show here that one is variable strictness. “S knows p” is commonly used loosely to implicate “S is close enough to knowing p for contextually indicated purposes.” A pragmatic account may use a range of semantics, even contextualist. I use an invariant semantics on which knowledge requires complete justification. This combination meets the Moorean constraint as well as any linguistic theory should, and meets the intuition constraint much better than contextualism. There is no need for ad hoc error theories. The variation in conditions of assertability and practical rationality is better explained by variably strict constraints. It will follow that “S knows p” is used loosely to implicate that the condition for asserting “p” and using it in practical reasoning are satisfied.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Atlas, J. D. (1977). Negation, ambiguity, and presupposition. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 321–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J. D. (1979). How linguistics matters to philosophy: Presupposition, truth, and meaning. In C.-K. Oh, & D. A. Dinneen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, 11: Presupposition. New York: Academic Press, pp. 265-281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J. D. (1989). Philosophy without ambiguity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1994). Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language, 9, 124-162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2000). Quantification, qualification and context: A reply to Stanley and Szabó. Mind and Language, 15, 262–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2001). Speaking loosely: Sentence nonliterality. In P. French, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy, 25, figurative language. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 249–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2005). The emperor’s new ‘knows’. In G. Preyer, & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 51–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2003). Context shifting arguments. Philosophical Perspectives, 17, 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1988). Implicature, explicature, and truth-theoretic semantics. In M. Kempson (Ed.), Mental representations: The interface between language and reality (pp. 155-81). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Reprinted In S. Davis (Ed.), Pragmatics: A reader (pp. 33-51). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1991).

  • Cohen, S. (1986). Knowledge and context. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 574–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthese, 73, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1988). How to be a fallibilist. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 91–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(Epistemology), 57–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2000a). Contextualism and skepticism. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 94–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2000b). Replies. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 132–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2001). Contextualism defended: Comments on Richard Feldman’s skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies, 103, 87–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2004). Knowledge, assertion, and practical reasoning. Philosophical Issues, 14(Epistemology), 482–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2005). Knowledge, speaker and subject. Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (1998). Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2004). Are knowledge claims indexical? Erkenntnis, 61, 267–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2005). Contextualist theories of knowledge. Acta Analytica, 20, 29–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 913–929.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review, 104, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1996a). Relevant alternatives and the content of knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56, 193–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1996b). Knowledge, assertion, and lotteries. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 568–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1999). Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In J. Greco, & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 187–205). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 126–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1971). Conclusive reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (1999). Contextualism and skepticism. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(Epistemology), 91–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogelin, R. J. (2000). Contextualism and externalism: Trading in one form of skepticism for another. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 43–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole, & J. Morgan (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 3: Speech acts. New York: Academic Press; Reprinted In H. P. Grice (Ed.), Studies in the Way of Words (pp. 22-40). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1989).

  • Grice, H. P. (1978). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 9: Pragmatics (pp. 113-128). New York: Academic Press. Reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words, ed. H. P. Grice, pp. 41-57. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1989).

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2000). Reply to Cohen. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 117–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004a). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004b). Replies. Philosophical Issues, 14(Epistemology), 510–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1999). Contextualism and anti-luck epistemology. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(Epistemology), 115–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofweber, T. (1999). Contextualism and the meaning intention problem. In K. Korta, E. Sosa, & J.␣Arrazola (Eds.), Cognition, agency, and rationality (pp. 93–104). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1979). On assertion and indicative conditionals. Philosophical Review, 88, 565–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2000). Contextualism and academic skepticism. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 108–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompa, N. (2002). The context sensitivity of knowledge ascriptions. Grazer-Philosophische Studien, 64, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompa, N. (2005). The semantics of knowledge ascriptions. Acta Analytica, 20, 16–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1977). Speaker reference and semantic reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 255–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. In R. Bäuerle et al. (Eds.), Semantics from different points of view (pp. 172–187). Berlin: Springer.

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow , P. (2005). Contextualism and the new linguistic turn in epistemology. In G. Preyer, & G.␣Peters (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy (pp. 11–50). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, N. (1952). Knowledge and belief. Mind, 51, 178–189.

  • Moore, G. E. (1962). Commonplace book: 1919–1953. London: Allen & Unwin.

  • Neale, S. (1992). Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (2004). Comments on Jason Stanley’s “On the linguistic basis for contextualism”. Philosophical Studies, 119, 147–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prades, J. L. (2000). Scepticism, contextualism, and closure. Philosophical Issues, 10(Skepticism), 121–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2005). Contextualism, skepticism, and warranted assertibility manoevres. In J. Keim-Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & H. Silverstein (Ed.), Knowledge and skepticism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs, 35, 477–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2006). The irrelevance of the subject: Against subject-sensitive invariantism. Philosophical Studies, 127, 87–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Contextualist solutions to scepticism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 317–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis of contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 119–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical inference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind and Language, 15, 219–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stine, G. (1976). Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure. Philosophical Studies, 29, 249–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1984). Philosophical relativity. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Unger, P. (1986). The cone model of knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 14, 125–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1999). The new relevant alternatives theory. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(Epistemology), 155–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the members of my Fall 2005 seminar, Emily Evans, Paul␣Naquin, Nate Olson, David Pierce, Mark Pitlyk, Diana Puglisi, and Dan Quattrone, for many hours of fruitful discussion in which many of the ideas of this paper were tried out or tested. Jason␣Stanley graciously providing the proofs of Knowledge and Practical Interest for us to work through. I am also grateful to Paul Portner and Elena Herburger for the opportunity to present part of this paper in their Spring 2006 seminar on implicature. Steven Gross also provided helpful comments. My greatest debt is to Stewart Cohen, who provided pages of extremely helpful and thought-provoking objections and replies. Attributions to Cohen without references were personal communications.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wayne A. Davis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Davis, W.A. Knowledge claims and context: loose use. Philos Stud 132, 395–438 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9035-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-006-9035-2

Keywords

Navigation