Skip to main content
Log in

Autism, intellectual disability, and a challenge to our understanding of proxy consent

  • Scientifc Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper focuses on a hypothetical case that represents an intervention request familiar to those who work with individuals with intellectual disability. Stacy has autism and moderate intellectual disability. Her parents have requested treatment for her hand flapping. Stacy is not competent to make her own treatment decisions; proxy consent is required. There are three primary justifications for proxy consent: the right to an open future, substituted judgment, and the best interest standard. The right to an open future justifies proxy consent on the assumption of future autonomy whereas substituted judgment justifies proxy consent via reference to past autonomy. Neither applies. Stacy has not been, nor will she be, competent to make her own treatment decisions. The best interest standard justifies proxy consent on the grounds of beneficence. It is unlikely that hand flapping harms Stacy. None of the three primary means of justifying proxy consent apply to Stacy’s case.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is a debate regarding the appropriate way to refer to those with autism. As I just did, one might use phrases like “people with autism” or “individuals with autism.” Alternatively, one might use the term “autistics.” Unfortunately, no matter which vocabulary I use, I will end up taking sides in a debate regarding which I have no considered view. I have chosen to use “people first” terminology; however, this should not be taken to be indicative of any stance I have in the relevant debate. I have to make some choice about the language I use. No matter which terminology I decide to employ, one side or the other will be unhappy.

  2. The word “treatment” presupposes a pathological view of Stacy’s stereotypy. Throughout the paper I will put the word in quotes to distance myself from the medical model of disability that the reader may take the word to imply.

  3. I am very grateful to Jessica Graber for drawing my attention to this concern.

  4. I am grateful to a reviewer for drawing my attention to this point.

References

  • Abizadeh, Arash. 2008. Democratic theory and border coercion no right to unilaterally control your own borders. Political theory 36(1): 37–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association. 2013. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5, 5th ed. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, Ron, and Shari Tresky. 2008. Bioethics and disability rights: Conflicting values and perspectives. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 5(2-3): 111–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aspies for Freedom. 2015. Aspies for freedom. Available at https://aspiesforfreedom.wordpress.com/about/.

  • Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2001. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cascio, M.Ariel. 2012. Neurodiversity: Autism pride among mothers of children with autism spectrum disorders. Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities 50(3): 273–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clapton, Jayne. 2003. Tragedy and catastrophe: Contentious discourses of ethics and disability. Journal of Intellectual Disability Research 47(7): 540–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, Allison B., and Laura Schreibman. 2008. Stereotypy in autism: The importance of function. Research in Autism Spectrum Disorders 2(3): 469–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D. 1997. Genetic dilemmas and a child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 27: 7–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durand, V., and E. Carr. 1987. Social influences on ‘‘self stimulatory’’ behavior: Analysis and treatment application. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis 20: 119–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1980. The child’s right to an open future. In Whose child? Children’s rights, parental authority, and state power, ed. W. Aiken, and H. LaFollette, 124–153. Totowa, NJ: Littlefield, Adams and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon, Raanan. 2003. Ethics needs principles—Four can encompass the rest—And respect for autonomy should be “first among equals”. Journal of Medical Ethics 29(5): 307–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, Kara, Brian A. Boyd, Jill V. Hamm, and Suzanne Kucharczyk. 2014. Supporting independence in adolescents on the autism spectrum. Remedial and Special Education 35(2): 102–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. 2011. How common is autism? Nature 474(7350): 166–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Jackie Leach Scully. 2007. Moral imagination, disability and embodiment. Journal of Applied Philosophy 24(4): 335–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Sarah, and Tammy Hedderly. 2014. A guide to childhood motor stereotypies, tic disorders and the tourette spectrum for the primary care practitioner. The Ulster Medical Journal 83(1): 22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, Sarah, Olive Healy, Sinéad Lydon, Laura Moran, and Ciara Foody. 2014. An analysis of treatment efficacy for stereotyped and repetitive behaviors in autism. Review Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 1(2): 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’neil, R. 1983. Determining proxy consent. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 8: 389–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pace, G., M. Ivancic, G. Edwards, et al. 1985. Assessment of stimulus preference and reinforcer value with profoundly retarded individuals. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis 18: 249–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piazza, C.C., J.D. Adelinis, G.P. Hanley, H.L. Goh, and M.D. Delia. 2000. An evaluation of the effects of matched stimuli on behaviors maintained by automatic reinforcement. Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis 33(1): 13–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, G., D. Stearsman, L. Campo-Engelstein, et al. 2012. Preserving the right to future children: An ethical case analysis. The American Journal of Bioethics 12: 38–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, John T., and Timothy R. Vollmer. 2005a. Stereotypy I: A review of behavioral assessment and treatment. Research in Developmental Disabilities 26(6): 527–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapp, John T., and Timothy R. Vollmer. 2005b. Stereotypy II: A review of neurobiological interpretations and suggestions for an integration with behavioral methods. Research in Developmental Disabilities 26(6): 548–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, Florence D.DiGennaro, Jason M. Hirst, and Sarah R. Hyman. 2012. Assessment and treatment of stereotypic behavior in children with autism and other developmental disabilities: A thirty year review. Research in Autism Spectrum Disorders 6(1): 422–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W.D. 1988. The right and the good. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, J. 2012. Don’t mourn for us. The Critical Journal of Interdisciplinary Autism Studies 1: 1–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soorya, L., J. Kiarashi, and E. Hollander. 2008. Psychopharmacologic interventions for repetitive behaviors in autism spectrum disorders. Child and Adolescent Psychiatric Clinics of North America 17: 753–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torke, A., G. Alexander, and J. Lantos. 2008. Substituted judgment: The limitations of autonomy in surrogate decision making. Journal of General Internal Medicine 23: 1514–1517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wehmeyer, Michael L. 1995. Intra-individual factors influencing efficacy of interventions for stereotyped behaviours: A meta-analysis. Journal of Intellectual Disability Research 39(3): 205–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper benefited greatly from the feedback of David Wacker, Wendy Berg, and Matt O'Brien. Above all, I am indepted to my brilliant wife, Jessica Graber. This paper comes out of our many discussions about ethics and disability and would not exist without both her insight and support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Abraham Graber.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Graber, A. Autism, intellectual disability, and a challenge to our understanding of proxy consent. Med Health Care and Philos 20, 229–236 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9745-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-016-9745-y

Keywords

Navigation