Skip to main content
Log in

Bioenhancements and the telos of medicine

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Staggering advances in biotechnology within the past decade have given rise to pharmacological, surgical and prosthetic techniques capable of enhancing human functioning rather than merely treating or preventing disease. Bioenhancement technologies range from nootropics capable of enhancing cognitive abilities to distraction osteogenesis, a surgical technique capable of increasing height through limb lengthening. This paper examines whether the use of bioenhancements falls inside or outside the proper boundaries of healthcare, and if so, whether clinicians have professional responsibilities to administer bioenhancements to patients. After explicating two theoretical approaches to the concept of health, one objectivist and the other constructivist, I contend that clinicians' corresponding professional responsibilities hinge on which philosophical account of health is endorsed, and illustrate how the lack of analytic clarity with respect to this concept can lead to defective positions on the place of bioenhancements in healthcare. With this conceptual framework in place, an account of health as a cluster concept that incorporates both constructivist and objectivist components is developed and defended.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also the Oath of Maimonides and the Declaration of Geneva, a declaration of medicine’s goals adopted by the World Medical Association (1948) that submits “The health of my patient will be my first consideration.”

  2. See Freedman (1978) and Walzer (1973) for discussion of these issues.

  3. These claims are revisited in “The inadequacy of objectivism” section where it is argued that they are not in fact value-neutral.

  4. This requires Boorse to take the position that determining whether a given process contributes to survival or reproduction ought to be done prospectively rather than retrospectively. For at some point in our history, our ancestors did require wisdom teeth and other vestigal structures for survival (wisdom teeth enabled consumption of tough meat tissue). Hence, on this view, functions aren’t explanations of why a process is present (contra Wright 1973) or how a process is integrated in a system (contra Cummins 1975) but rather are contributions to goal-attainment.

  5. Objectivists debate the status of psychological conditions. Szasz (Murphy 1987, 2011) argues that “mental disease is a myth” since it doesn’t consist in demonstrable physiological dysfunctions. Others (e.g., Murphy 2012) explain that mental disease is reducible to physiological dysfunction.

  6. The reason why this is formulated as a necessary but not as a sufficient condition is that it is conceivable that a clinician might aim to ensure/restore someone’s biological normality but in doing so end up leaving that person worse off. Whether such acts would constitute acts of healthcare hinges on whether acts of healthcare are circumscribed by agents’ intentions or the outcomes of agents’ actions viz. restoring/ensuring health. This issue, while important, is beyond the scope of this paper.

  7. Cf., January 2003 report of the President’s Bioethics Council, Beyond Therapy.

  8. See Cummins (1975).

  9. See n. 4.

  10. The hybrid approach discussed here might be considered an informed-desire satisfaction theory (Cf. Alexandrova (2005), Murphy (2012)).

  11. The authorship of the Oath of Maimonides is contested; some claim that the Oath was penned not by Maimonides but by Marcus Hertz (1747–1802), pupil of Immanuel Kant and friend and physician of Moses Mendelssohn. For a detailed history, see Rosner (1998).

References

  • Alexandrova, A. 2005. Subjective well-being and Kahneman’s ‘objective happiness’. Journal of Happiness Studies 6: 301–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arden, N., and M.C. Nevitt. 2006. Osteoarthritis: Epidemiology. Best Practice & Research Clinical Rheumatology 20(1): 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1977. Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44: 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. 1997. A rebuttal on health. In What is disease?, ed. J.M. Humber, and R.F. Almeder, 1–134. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press.

  • Boorse, Christopher. 2014. A second rebuttal on health. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39(6): 683–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boss, Medard. 1983. Existential foundations of medicine and psychology. New York: J. Aronson.

  • Bostrom, N. 2007. Dignity and enhancement. In Human dignity and bioethics: Essays commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethics, ed. President's Council on Bioethics, 1–32. Washington, DC: U.S. Government.

  • Buchanan, Allan, et al. 2000. From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, A., and H.T. Englehardt. 1981. Concepts of health and disease: Interdisciplinary perspectives. Reading, Mass: Addison-Wesley, Advanced Book Program/World Science Division.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel, H., and R. Cooper. 2014. Health, illness and disease: Philosophical essays. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. 1975. Functional analysis. The Journal of Philosophy 72: 741–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, Charles. 1898. The descent of man: And selection in relation to sex. Appleton.

  • Engelhardt, H.T. 2012. Bioethics and secular humanism: the search for a common morality. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenton, Elizabeth. 2008. Genetic enhancement—a threat to human rights? Bioethics 22: 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, Benjamin. 1978. A meta-ethics for professional morality. Ethics 89(1): 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, F. 2004. Transhumanism. Foreign Policy 144: 42–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingma, E. 2007. What is it to be healthy? Analysis 67: 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, Margaret. 2000. Cosmetic Surgery, Suspect Norms, and the Ethics of Complicity. In Enhancing human traits: Ethical and social implications, ed. E. Parens, 162–176. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Dominic. 2012. Psychiatry in the scientific image. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest. 1979. The structure of science : Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Newson, Ainsley J., and Richard E. Ashcroft. 2005. Whither authenticity? The American Journal of Bioethics 5(3): 53–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, Lennart Y. 1995. On the nature of health: An action-theoretic approach. Vol. 26. New York: Springer Science & Business Media.

  • Nordenfelt, Lennart. 1996. The goals and limits of medicine. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell.

  • Nordenfelt, Lennart. 2001. Health, science, and ordinary language. No. 110. Rodopi.

  • Nordenfelt, Lennart. 2007. The concepts of health and illness revisited. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 10(1): 5–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordenfelt, Lennart. 2009. Health, autonomy and quality of life. In Dignity in care for older people, ed. M.R. Matiti, and L. Baillie. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell.

  • Pellegrino, Edmund. 2004. Biotechnology, human enhancement, and the ends of medicine. Dignity 10: 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radoilska, Lubomira. 2010. An aristotelian approach to cognitive enhancement. Journal of Value Inquiry 44: 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosner, Fred. 1998. The medical legacy of Moses Maimonides. Hoboken, NJ: Ktav Publishing House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, Michael. 2004. The case against perfection. The Atlantic Monthly 293(3): 51–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T.S. 1987. Insanity: The idea and its consequences. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szasz, T.S. 2011. The myth of mental illness: 50 years later. The Psychiatrist 35(5): 179–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svenaeus, F. 2001. The phenomenology of health and illness. In Handbook of phenomenology and medicine, vol. 68, ed. S.K. Toombs, 87–108. Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1991. The ethics of authenticity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1973. Political action: The problem of dirty hands. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2(2): 160–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Medical Association. 1948. The declaration of Geneva. Reprinted in Encyclopedia of Bioethics (1995:2647), Volume 5. Ed. Reich, W.T., New York: Simon and Schuster.

  • Young, M.J. 2014. Ethics and ontology in deep brain stimulation. AJOB Neuroscience 5(1): 34–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael J. Young.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Young, M.J. Bioenhancements and the telos of medicine. Med Health Care and Philos 18, 515–522 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-015-9634-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-015-9634-9

Keywords

Navigation