Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Happiness, Dispositions and the Self

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Happiness Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue that happiness is an exclusively categorical mental state. Daniel Haybron’s inclusion of dispositions into his emotional state theory rests of a confusion of constituents of happiness in the narrow psychological sense with objects of prudential concern, to which obviously belong “mood propensities” and other dispositional states. I further argue that while it is probably correct to require of a constituent of happiness that it must in some sense be “deep” and belong to, or directly impact on, a persons’ self, the importance of depth may be overrated by the emotional state theory, which also ignores the possibility that mental states other than moods and emotions can be deep in the relevant sense.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are, however, quite a few conceptions of happiness that are non-psychological or at least not purely psychological. Some philosophers, notably in the Aristotelian tradition, have insisted on viewing happiness as an evaluative, most often moral, notion. Still more have, as a matter of fact, treated it as something that comprises both psychological and normative aspects. I shall only be concerned with happiness in a purely psychological sense (see also Sect. 3).

  2. For a defence of the existence of nonphenomenal conscious states (see Nelkin 1989; Lormand 1996; Peacocke 2003; Georgalis 2005). Especially conscious propositional attitudes (e.g. acts of thinking) have been having no distinctive phenomenal character in themselves, but merely being—very often—accompanied by other states that have such a character (e.g. conscious imagining, thinking “in words” etc.). However, a majority of philosophers of mind seem to think that conscious states are necessarily phenomenal (Strawson 1994; Siewert 1998; Levine 2001; Dainton 2008; Farkas 2008; Kriegel 2009). For a defence of the view that propositional attitudes have a distinctive phenomenal character (see Klausen 2008).

  3. Although, as Haybron himself notes (Haybron 2008, p. 285, n. 6), affect-based empirical research on happiness, notably the work of Kahneman, has also recognized the relevance of moods and emotions.

  4. If moods and emotions are themselves conceived as (partly) dispositional, it seems that a mood propensity must be second-order disposition, viz. a disposition to (inter alia) acquire other, more specific dispositions. This might seem somewhat strange, but need not be considered unreasonable; arguably, quite a few significant psychological or moral traits take the form of second-order dispositions. Moreover, Haybron seems to restrict the relevant manifestations of mood propensities to the phenomenal (and thus categorical) aspects of moods, when he speaks of a disposition to experience moods.

  5. In one place, Haybron even says that happiness “primarily concerns a person’s psychic dispositions” (2008, p. 69). This does not sit quite well with his suggestion that occurrent states should have priority over dispositional one’s when assessing a person’s happiness.

  6. This seems to contradict Haybron’s claim that happiness cannot be purely dispositional. But I understand him as allowing for the possibility that happiness may be temporarily (“locally”) made up by purely dispositional states. His admission that happiness must involve some occurrent states appears to be nothing more than a kind of (“global”) system requirement: a happy person must sometimes have some characteristic experiences. This is consistent with the possibility that her happiness is purely dispositional some, or even most, of the time.

  7. I would be more cautious with judging Martha to be happy, not merely because of the alleged difference between the concepts of temperament and happiness, but also because the link between behavioral dispositions and the affective states required for happiness can be rather weak.

  8. Haybron briefly notes this possibility, but seems to think that is at best an unusual practice (Haybron 2008, p. 34).

  9. The notion of a propensity has proved extremely difficult to define precisely (see Belnap 2007 for an overview). For present purposes it should suffice to notice that while not identical to probabilities of outcomes, propensities are closely similar to such probabilities, and are regularly used to explain probabilities and ground predictions about the frequency of events. Moreover, it is generally assumed that a propensity to yield an outcome E obtains if and only if it is the case that outcome E would be produced in a sufficiently large and varied number of cases (paraphrasing Alston 2005, p. 110).

  10. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for helping me to clarify this point.

  11. The case thus complies with Haybron’s—somewhat ad hoc—constraint that mood propensities not be tied to specific objects.

  12. Hill (2009, 220f.) makes a similar point about some of Haybron’s other examples.

  13. Contrary to what Feldman (2010, 29ff.) appears to assume.

  14. It can be questioned whether this suggestion conforms with Haybron’s requirement that happiness-constitutive mood propensities must be emotionally based. But perhaps it could be argued that Jane’s mood propensities are grounded in her emotional condition (which, in turn, is maintained by the intervention of her friends and relatives).

  15. But ask Proust about eating a Madeleine. While it can be argued that the pleasure of his narrator—famously described at the beginning of In Search of Lost Time—only causally triggered an array of other, allegedly more central mental states, it did seem to have a rather deep significance in itself.

  16. Correspondingly, there is empirical evidence that even fleeting, superficial mood states can have a highly significant and predictable influence on people’s behavior and self-understanding (Forgas and Williams 2002, p. 74). This may be due to their being correlated with more central states, but still indicates that they are themselves more significant than might otherwise be expected.

  17. See Feldman (2010, 52ff.; 72ff.); Haybron (2008, Ch. 5).

  18. I shall ignore the possibility that there can be states that are non-phenomenally conscious (but see footnote 2).

  19. I have assumed that dispositional states are essentially unconscious (though the may be constituted by their tendency to produce conscious experiences). But it is possible that some dispositional states do have a distinctive phenomenology (though this may better be seen as an accompanying categorical state). Being irritable or cheerful may have a certain feel of to it (Klausen 2008; cf. also Feldman 2010, p. 142). This phenomenal side of dispositions could of course be directly relevant to happiness. But again, this is because it is a conscious experience and has nothing do with dispositionality as such.

  20. It may be objected on Haybron’s behalf that he is does not intend to simply analyze the folk concept of happiness (Haybron 2008, p. 47), and that it is therefore less important if our intuitions do not favor the inclusion of unconscious states into that concept. But Haybron obviously does think that this inclusion is in agreement with, and perhaps even motivated by, ordinary usage. A more revisionary approach would be more open to the inclusion of e.g. character traits or brain processes.

  21. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

  22. Work on this paper was supported by the EU Interreg 4A Program, in the context of the NexusPro2017 project. I am also grateful to Lina Lind Christensen and other graduate students who attended my seminar on Welfare, Happiness and the Good Life at the University of Southern Denmark in the spring of 2014 for valuable suggestions, and to two anonymous reviewers for their insight and perceptive criticisms.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2005). Beyond ‘Justification’. Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. (2007). Propensities and probabilities. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38, 593–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (1998). Dispositions and antidotes. The Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 227–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1997). Two kinds of consciousness. In N. Block, et al. (Eds.), The Nature of Consciousness (pp. 427–433). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, P. T., & McCrae, R. R. (1980). Influence of extraversion and neuroticism on subjective well-being: Happy and unhappy people. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 38(4), 668–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2002). Elements of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. (2006). Reasons and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2008). The phenomenal self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2002). Well-being and rational care. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daudet, A. (2002). In the land of pain (1930) (ed. and transl. by Julian Barnes). New York: Knopf.

  • Diener, E., & Lucas, R. E. (1999). Personality and subjective well-being. In D. Kahneman, E. Diener, & N. Schwarz (Eds.), 1999. Well-being. The foundation of hedonic psychology. New York: Russell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2008). The subject’s point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (2010). What is this thing called happiness? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Forgas, J. P., & Williams, K. D. (Eds.). (2002). The social self: Individual, interpersonal and intergroup perspectives. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgalis, N. (2005). The primacy of the subjective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2001). Happiness and pleasure. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 501–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2005). On being happy or unhappy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 287–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness. The elusive psychology of well-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2010). Mood propensity as a constituent of happiness. A rejoinder to hill. Journal of Happiness Studies, 11, 19–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, S. (2009). Haybron on mood propensity and happiness. Journal of Happiness Studies, 10, 215–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2006). Virtuous acts, virtuous dispositions. Analysis, 66, 69–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klausen, S. H. (2004). Reality lost and found. An essay on the realism-antirealism controversy. Odense: University Press of Southern Denmark

  • Klausen, S. H. (2008). The phenomenology of propositional attitudes. Journal of Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 445–462.

  • Klausen, S. H. (2013). Losing belief, while keeping up the attitudes: the case for cognitive phenomenology. In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New Essays on Belief (pp. 188–208). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness. A self-representational theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lormand, E. (1996). Nonphenomenal consciousness. Nous, 30, 242–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maltz, W. (Ed.). (2009). Intimate kisses. The poetry of sensual pleasure. Novato, CA: New World Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, N. (1989). Propositional attitudes and consciousness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 49(3), 413–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2003). Conscious attitudes, attention and self-knowledge. In Brie Gertler (Ed.), Privileged access philosophical accounts of self-knowledge (pp. 83–110). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions. A perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, Eric. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36, 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1996). Valuing emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1994). Mental reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Søren Harnow Klausen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Klausen, S.H. Happiness, Dispositions and the Self. J Happiness Stud 17, 995–1013 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-015-9628-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10902-015-9628-6

Keywords

Navigation