Skip to main content
Log in

How to do things with nonwords: pragmatics, biosemantics, and origins of language in animal communication

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent discussions of animal communication and the evolution of language have advocated adopting a ‘pragmatics-first’ approach, according to which “a more productive framework” for primate communication research should be “pragmatics, the field of linguistics that examines the role of context in shaping the meaning of linguistic utterances” (Wheeler and Fischer, Evol Anthropol 21:195–205, 2012: 203). After distinguishing two different conceptions of pragmatics that advocates of the pragmatics-first approach have implicitly relied on (one Carnapian, the other Gricean), I argue that neither conception adequately serves the purposes of pragmatics-first approaches to the origins of human linguistic communication. My main aim in this paper is to motivate–and begin to articulate–an intermediary conception whose scope is narrower than Carnapian pragmatics but broader than Gricean pragmatics. To do so, I first spell out what I take to be the key insight offered by proponents of the Gricean approach concerning the emergence of linguistic communication, namely, its being communication ‘from a psychological point of view’ (Tomasello, Origins of human communication, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, 2008). I then develop this insight using key elements from the anti-Gricean ‘biosemantic’ account of linguistic communication due to Ruth Millikan (Millikan, Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism, MIT Press, Cambridge MA, 1984, Millikan, Tomberlin (ed), Philosophical Perspectives 9, Ridgeview Publishing, Atascedero CA, 1995, Millikan R (2006) Varieties of Meaning. Mass.: The MIT Press (paperback edition), Cambridge, Millikan, Beyond concepts: unicepts, language, and natural information, Oxford University Press, Oxford UK, 2017, and elsewhere). I argue that the intermediary pragmatics-first approach that I propose, which draws on both Gricean and Millikanian resources, would be better equipped to serve the purposes of those who search for potential precursors of human linguistic communication in animal communication.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Bach (1997), Recanati (2002), Carston (2008).

  2. For an illuminating discussion, see Millikan, e.g. (1984: 39–49,116–117); (1995: 190); (2017: Ch. 11).

  3. As explained in Bar-On (under review), the proponents ought to give some evidence that primate call interpreters are sensitive to at least some aspects of ‘wide’ context (as understood in Recanati 2002).

  4. Bar-On (under review) develops this argument in connection with the formal semantic-pragmatic analysis of monkey calls offered in Schlenker et al. (2014) and elsewhere.

  5. Although Grice himself may well not have been committed to the ‘psychological reality’ of his proposed analysis, proponents of a Gricean pragmatics-first approach deploy the Gricean conception precisely to extract cognitive requirements that would have to be met by any legitimate precursor of human linguistic communication. (For relevant discussion, see Bar-On 1995, 2013.).

  6. See Sperber & Wilson (1986/1995) and Sperber & Wilson (2015); see also Moore (2017).

  7. See, e.g., Moore (2017) and (2018). Notably, however, Moore’s ‘minimally Gricean’ communication is still ostensive communication; so it may still set the bar too high for a pragmatics-first approach. (And see fn. 10 below).

  8. He adds: “Evidence for this interpretation is that on some occasions apes will actually hide a display from others, for example, covering up a facial fear-grimace display with their hands” (ibid.).

    An anonymous referee has pointed out, however, that some researchers (e.g. Hobaiter and Byrne 2014) deny that there is any category of great ape gestures that are used only to solicit attention.

  9. We could also separate a third strand: the idea that what meaningful signs standardly or conventionally mean is ultimately dependent upon what speakers mean by them. (For some discussion and references, see Bar-On 1995.)

  10. Moore’s (2018) ‘minimally Gricean’ communicators are still said to engage in ostensive-inferential communication. They produce utterances with ‘overt’ (i.e., ostensive) ‘communicative intent’; and their receivers are said to attribute intentions to producers and to make inferences about their mental states. It is just that Moore thinks this becomes less cognitively demanding once we abandon Grice’s ‘third-clause’ on speaker meaning, with its fourth-order meta-representations (2018: 8f.) (something that had already been advocated by Neale 1992; and see also, e.g., Sperber & Wilson 2015). By contrast, the intermediary conception I propose below would allow us to divorce the origins of meaningful communication from the presence of even ‘minimally Gricean’ speaker meaning.

  11. Cheney & Seyfarth (2003), Marler (2004), and Snowdon (2008) suggest that the innate and expressive or ‘emotional’ character of calls and other displays is consistent with their having at least functionally referential dimensions. Bar-On (2013) and (2018) argues that the expressive character of calls and other signals is consistent with call users bringing their production under voluntary control and using them intentionally and mindfully.

    As an anonymous referee has remarked, those who advocate a construal of chimpanzee (or other) communication as ‘intentional and minded’ need to establish that chimpanzees rely on representations of each other’s psychological states as opposed to their (anticipated) behaviors. On the Millikanian view to be proposed below (“Psychologically mediated communication: an integrated view”), this would be a matter to be determined by the proper function of the relevant representations. It is arguably a plausible hypothesis that social creatures harbor representations whose proper function is to represent each other’s psychological states. But, on Millikan’s view, this does not mean they have conceptual or theoretical understanding of mental states.

  12. For an illuminating discussion of related experiments to show that chimpanzees meet criteria for intentional (though not fully Gricean) communication, see Schel et al. (2013).

  13. Millikan’s notion of proper function covers what Maynard Smith & Harper refer to as “indices”, as well as “handicaps” (2003: 15). Indeed, Millikan’s 1984 account is, by design, applicable to a very wide range of biological representational devices, including e.g., the magnetosomes that guide certain bacteria to oxygen-poor waters by directing them to magnetic north (2006: 82), as well as signals produced and consumed by sub-systems inside organisms. (See also, e.g. 2006: Ch. 13.).

  14. To be precise, it is correct animal signals (i.e., ones that map onto existing states of affairs) that can serve as natural signs of what they represent.

  15. A complication I am here setting aside is Millikan’s claim that, unlike indicative and imperative utterances, animal representations are (all or most) ‘pushmi-pullyu’ representations. (See e.g. 1995 and 2006: 80ff. and passim. And see Bar-On (under review) for discussion.)

  16. Millikan’s claim here should only be taken to imply that thinking about others’ mental states is not essential to the use of meaningful language, and, by implication, would not have had to precede the emergence of language.

  17. As noted earlier (Sect. 1), this means that a post-Gricean account of the emergence of linguistic communication would incur a problematic burden: to provide an evolutionary explanation of some of the very same capacities whose emergence it seeks to explain–viz., the capacities to form and interpret language-like compositional, recursive, and metarepresentational thoughts (and other propositional attitudes).

  18. In the next section, I provide some possible illustrations from existing forms of animal communication.

  19. See Millikan (1984: Ch. 10) for the relevant notion of improvisation in connection with the analysis of indexicals. Millikan discusses the main implications of her view for the acquisition of language in, e.g., (2006: Ch. 10, esp. pp. 128–133) and (2017: Chapters 13–14, esp. pp. 196–198).

  20. Relevant here are arguments by e.g. de Villiers (2000) for the developmental dependence of the relevant metarepresentational and conceptual capacities on the mastery of certain linguistic structures.

  21. Clearly much more needs to be said about the nature of the dog’s representation of the squirrel’s intention and, more generally, about the possibility of representing mental states without having concepts of–or beliefs about–them. For Millikan, this possibility requires understanding the role of pushmi-pullyu representations (mentioned in footnote 15) in animal cognition as combined with the deployment of what in her (2017) she dubs ‘unicepts’. For relevant discussion, see her (1995), (2017: 7.6 and passim), and (2006: esp. Part IV).

    Millikan’s view on these matters departs from tradition in a number of important ways. But in the present context, the main point that bears emphasis is this. By seeking to establish whether or not infants and nonhuman animals possess a theory of mind (and by taking the representation of mental states to require some conceptual/theoretical understanding of minds) researchers are imposing on the representation of mental states standards that many in philosophy of language and mind believe we should not impose on representation more generally.

  22. Recently, Scarantino has suggested that we can think of what animals do with emotion expressions (including alarm calls) in terms of “analogs” of Austinian speech acts. However, Scarantino himself presents his ‘theory of affective pragmatics’ as “pragmatic in the Carnapian sense only: It aims to capture how the meaning of emotional expressions depends [narrowly] on their context of production…” (2017: 217, emphasis added). It is thus consistent with his view that expressive communication is fully coded communication.

  23. See Progovac (2017) for a systematic and illuminating development of the idea of Protolanguage from a broadly Chomskian perspective on language.

  24. A fuller discussion would, of course, need to make good on the claim made here that the relevant psychological give-and-take need not rely on Gricean mindreading capacities. (See Bar-On (under review) and ms. in-progress.)

  25. It would not even need to appeal to a capacity for ‘minimal Gricean’ communication (as described by, e.g., Moore (2018)–which still relies on overt communicative intentions on the part of speakers and their inferential attribution to speakers by their hearers (see footnote 10 above).

  26. The following description follows Arnold & Bar-On (2020). Bar-On (under review, mentioned in footnote 4 above) offers a critical discussion of a contextual semantic-pragmatic analysis of putty-nosed monkeys’ calls that does not incorporate the features highlighted here under ‘mind-dependence’.

  27. A different–though potentially compatible–‘dynamic’ construal of monkey calls (utilizing Stalnaker’s notion of a ‘common ground’) is proposed in Armstrong (2018: 13f.).

References

  • Armstrong J (2018) Provincialism in pragmatics. Phil Perspect 32(1):5–40

  • Arnold K, Bar-On D (2020) Primate pragmatics, expressive Behavior, and the evolution of language. Animal Behav Cognit 7(2):117–130

  • Arnold K, Zuberbühler K (2012) Call combinations in monkeys: compositional or idiomatic expressions? Brain Lang 120(3):303–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold K, Zuberbühler K (2013) Female putty-nosed monkeys use experimentally altered contextual information to disambiguate the cause of male alarm calls. PLOS ONE 8(6):e65660

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (1997) The semantics-pragmatics distinction. Linguistische Berichte 8:33–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On D (1995) Reconstructing ‘meaning’: Grice and the naturalization of semantics. Pac Philos Q 76:83–116

  • Bar-On D (2013) Origins of meaning: must we ‘go Gricean’? Mind Lang 28(3):342–375

  • Bar-On D (2018) Gricean intentions, expressive communication, and origins of meaning” In: Andrews K, Beck J (eds) The routledge companion to the philosophy of animal minds. Routledge, New York, NY, pp 301-312

  • Bar-On D, Moore R (2018) Pragmatic interpretation and signaler-receiver asymmetries in animal communication. In Andrews K, Beck, J (eds) The Routledge companion to the philosophy of animal minds, Routledge, New York, NY, pp 291–300

  • Breheny R (2006) Communication and folk psychology. Mind Lang 21:74–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burling R (2005) The talking ape. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1942) Introduction to semantics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston R (2008) Linguistic communication and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Synthese 165:321–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston R (2015) Pramatics and semantics. The oxford handbook of pragmatics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 453–472

    Google Scholar 

  • Crockford C et al (2012) Wild chimpanzees inform ignorant group members of danger”. Curr Biol 22(2):142–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckardt W, Zuberbühler K (2004) Cooperation and competition in two forest monkeys. Behav Ecol 15:400–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch T (2010) The evolution of language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1957) Meaning. Philos Rev 66(3):377–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1968) Utterer’s meaning, sentence-meaning, and word-meaning. Found Lang 4:225–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1989) Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobaiter C, Byrne R (2014) The meanings of chimpanzee gestures. Curr Biol 24(14):1596–1600

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurford J (2007) The origins of meaning: Language in the light of evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff J (2002) Foundations of language. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marler P (2004) Bird calls: a cornucopia for communication. In: Marler P, Slabbekoorn H (eds) Nature’s music: the science of Birdsong. Elsevier, San Diego, CA, pp 132–177

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1989) Biosemantics. J Philos 86(6):281–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1995) Pushmi-pullyu representations. In: Tomberlin J (ed) Philosophical perspectives 9. Ridgeview Publishing, Atascedero CA, pp 185–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2017) Beyond concepts: unicepts, language, and natural information. Oxford University Press, Oxford UK

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2004) On reading signs: some differences between us and the others. In: Kimbrough Oller D, Griebel U (eds) Evolution of communication systems, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 15–30

  • Millikan R (2006) Varieties of meaning. The MIT Press (paperback edition), Mass, Cambridge

  • Moore R (2018) Gricean communication, language development, and animal minds. Philos Compass 13(12):e12550

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore R (2017) Convergent minds: ostension, inference and Grice’s third clause. In: Clayton et al (eds) Interface focus vol 7, p 20160107

  • Neal S (1992) Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguist Phil 15:509–559

  • Oller D, Griebel U (2008) Evolution of communicative flexibility. MIT University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Origgi G, Sperber D (2000) Evolution, communication, and the proper function of language. In: Carruthers P, Chamberlain A (eds) Evolution and the human mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 140–169

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Progovac L (2017) Evolutionary syntax. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2002) Does linguistic communication rest on inference? Mind Lang 17:105–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino A (2017) Twelve questions for the theory of affective pragmatics. Psychol Inquiry 28(2–3):217–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schel AM et al (2013) Chimpanzee alarm call production meets key criteria for intentionality. PLoS ONE 8(10):1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker P et al (2014) Monkey semantics. Linguist Philos 37(6):439–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips TC (2015) Speaking Our Minds. Palgrave Macmillian, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth RM, Cheney D (2003) Meaning and emotion in animal vocalizations. Ann NY Acad Sci 1000:32–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D (2017) The origin of meaning in animal signals. Anim Behav 124:339–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon C (2008) Contextually Flexible Communication in Nonhuman Primates. In: Oller and Griebel (eds) pp. 71–92

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1986/1995) Relevance: communication and cognition, 2nd ed. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (2015) Beyond speaker meaning. Croatian J Philos 44:117–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2008) Origins of human communication. MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Villiers de J (2000) Language and theory of mind. In: Baron-Cohen et al (eds) Understanding other minds, pp 83–123

  • Wheeler BC, Fischer J (2012) Functionally referential signs. Evol Anthropol 21(5):195–205. https://doi.org/10.1002/evan.21319

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of parts of this paper have been presented at the following venues: ZAS conference on primate linguistics (Berlin, March 2019), Expression, Communication, and Origins of Meaning (ECOM) Research Group conference on communication, context, conversation, University of Connecticut (May 2019), a conference on thought, language, and communication, Zurich, Switzerland and Psychology Department colloquium at Sheffield, UK (September 2019), the New York Philosophy of Language workshop (October 2019), and the Evolutionary Pragmatics Forum (October 2020). I wish to thank the audiences at these presentations, as well as members of the Summer 2018 and Spring 2021 Ruth Millikan reading groups (organized under the auspices of the ECOM Research Group), for helpful discussions. Kate Arnold, Nimra Asif, Drew Johnson, Bill Lycan, Keith Simmons, and Alison Springle provided very useful feedback on various draft, which helped shape the present version of the paper. I owe special thanks to Robyn Carston for insightful comments and several pivotal discussions. Finally, my gratitude to Ruth Millikan for her ground-breaking work, for her philosophical and personal inspiration, and for several discussions that informed the view articulated in the present paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dorit Bar-On.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bar-On, D. How to do things with nonwords: pragmatics, biosemantics, and origins of language in animal communication. Biol Philos 36, 50 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09824-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-021-09824-z

Keywords

Navigation