Skip to main content
Log in

Evolutionary forces and the Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium has been argued by Sober, Stephens and others to represent the zero-force state for evolutionary biology understood as a theory of forces. I investigate what it means for a model to involve forces, developing an explicit account by defining what the zero-force state is in a general theoretical context. I use this account to show that Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium is not the zero-force state in biology even in the contexts in which it applies, and argue based on this that drift should not be understood as an evolutionary force.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This simplifies Aristotelian physics. Actual Aristotelian mechanics doesn’t have a fully coherent treatment of rates of change. Our discussion of Aristotelian mechanics here will therefore be a somewhat idealized and anachronistic one, as suits our need to draw a particular conceptual contrast with Newtonian mechanics. The issue is that a fully coherent ‘Aristotelian’ view such as is presented here conflicts too obviously with empirical evidence. In particular, how velocity changes after a force is removed is a problem that historically meets various attempted solutions, which make the mechanics more empirically adequate but less conceptually pure; this account ignores these solutions. The difficulty can be understood as a tension between the idea that velocity must proportional to the force applied and should be zero in the absence of a force (which is key to our treatment of Aristotelianism), with the observation that a thrown object loses its velocity gradually, even though the force would appear to cease once the thrown object leaves the hand.

  2. As well as the resistance to that force: in Aristotelian mechanics, the resistance of the medium is always factored into the velocity.

  3. To be more precise, we might say that the magnitude of the force is the absolute value of the variable, since whether the variable is positive or negative just tells us the direction in which the force acts.

  4. The difference is just that parameters aren’t subject to experimental manipulations—e.g. the gravitational constant.

References

  • Gillespie JH (2001) Is the population size of a species relevant to its evolution? Evolution 55:2161–2169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisler IL, Damuth J (1987) A method for analyzing selection in hierarchically structured populations. Am Nat 130:582–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock C, Velasco JD (2014) Evolutionary and newtonian forces. Ergo 1:39–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2010) The natures of selection. Br J Philos Sci 61:313–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. J Philos 44:55–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2005) How to understand causal relations in natural selection: reply to Rosenberg and Bouchard. Biol Philos 20:355–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M, Ariew A (2009) Selection and causation. Philos Sci 76:201–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea DW, Brandon RN (2010) Biology’s first law: the tendency for diversity and complexity to increase in evolutionary systems. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein RL (2002) Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct? Biol Philos 17:33–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reisman K, Forber P (2005) Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philos Sci 72:1113–1123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Shapiro L (2007) Epiphenomenalism: The do’s and the don’ts. In: Wolters G, Machamer PK (eds) Studies in causality: historical and contemporary. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C (2004) Selection, drift, and the “Forces” of evolution. Philos Sci 71:550–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C (2010) Forces and causes in evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 77:716–727

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2004) Bookkeeping or metaphysics? The units of selection debate. Synthese 138:337–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2007) The pomp of superfluous causes: the interpretation of evolutionary theory. Philos Sci 74:281–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM (2013) Descriptions and models: some responses to abrams. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 44:302–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh DM, Lewens T, Ariew A (2002) The trials of life: natural selection and random drift. Philos Sci 69:452–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen. Oxford University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Denis Walsh, Samir Okasha, Jacob Stegenga, Philippe Huneman, Cory Lewis, Alex Djedovic, Fermin Fulda, Michael Cournoyea, Christopher Stephens and an anonymous reviewer for their helpful comments and encouragement.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eugene Earnshaw.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Earnshaw, E. Evolutionary forces and the Hardy–Weinberg equilibrium. Biol Philos 30, 423–437 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9464-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9464-9

Keywords

Navigation