Skip to main content
Log in

Enabling conditions for ‘open-ended evolution’

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we review and argue for the relevance of the concept of open-ended evolution in biological theory. Defining it as a process in which a set of chemical systems bring about an unlimited variety of equivalent systems that are not subject to any pre-determined upper bound of organizational complexity, we explain why only a special type of self-constructing, autonomous systems can actually implement it. We further argue that this capacity derives from the ‘dynamic decoupling’ (in its minimal or most basic sense: the phenotype–genotype decoupling) by means of which a radically new way of material organization (minimal living organization) is achieved, allowing for the long-term sustenance of systems whose individual-metabolic and collective-historical pathways become thereafter deeply intertwined.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the case of development, understood as «a process whereby a relatively unspecified system comprised of loosely connected lower level parts becomes organized into a coherent, higher-level agency» (Coffman 2006), one could interpret that there is also some sort of ‘evolutionary pathway’, with an overall increase in the complexity of the system, but this would be restricted to an individual organism and its lifetime. The problem is really much more complicated, because development is, in fact, tightly linked to evolution, in that wider and more common, biological sense of the term. Nevertheless, here we will not deal with it: we will focus on the actual conditions for the origin of evolution as a long-term process of change (that takes place in a population of historically related systems), before proper developmental systems appeared.

  2. The terms ‘full-fledged living being’ and ‘infrabiological system’ are here used to make the distinction between living systems as we know them and certain (hypothetical) ones with a significantly lower degree of complexity (see also (Szathmary et al. 2005)). Some of us have discussed more extensively the criteria to define life elsewhere (Ruiz-Mirazo et al. 2004), which would mainly cover metabolic (‘autonomous’) and Darwinian (‘open-ended’) evolution capacities. These are very demanding conditions, so in the process of origins of life (or any artificial reconstruction of it) there must necessarily be systems below the threshold. In our account open-ended evolution will be the last condition for prebiotic systems to become proper living ones, so the beginning of open-ended evolution would be equivalent to the end of the process of origins of life.

  3. Our use of the term ‘mechanism’ (following (Bechtel 2005)) is not reductionist: i.e., it is not restricted to local and deterministic molecular devices, but includes more global and emergent organizational principles.

  4. The term ‘functional’ will be used in this paper in a very broad sense, to describe an action of a part of a system/organization (or a relation between different parts of that system/organization) that contributes to its global self-maintenance (Moreno et al. 1994).

  5. We will distinguish the terms ‘replication’ and ‘reproduction’ following Dyson (1985), Fleischaker (1994) and Luisi (1994): i.e., restricting the use of replication for the ‘copying’ of a specific molecular structure in which sequence is conserved, and taking ‘reproduction’ as a more general term (close to the idea of multiplication) that can be applied to global organizations. This distinction is not widely spread yet, although more and more researchers are becoming aware of its importance (see, e.g.: (Szathmáry and Maynard Smith 1997; Griesemer 2000; Szathmáry 2006)).

  6. In other words, we hold the view that, even if sex or conscious intelligence had never arisen (given different circumstances from the ones life has endured on Earth), the type of evolutionary pathway followed by living organisms (also assuming that these remained unicellular) would still be fully open-ended.

  7. So our approach does not exclude the possibility that, previous to the appearance of a process of open-ended evolution, there were other types of ‘selective dynamics’ among the members of a population of reproducing and interacting systems. On the contrary, it demands that there actually were. However, we do not agree with authors that tend to consider all of these dynamics as ground for natural selection processes ((Maynard Smith 1986; Szathmáry 2000)). If the mechanism of diversification is just the arbitrary variation of any component/set of components of the system, if multiplication simply takes place by autocatalytic growth and statistical division, if heredity can only be understood as a kind of ‘compositional invariance’ through generations (Segré et al. 2000), or if the fitness function (selection criterion) is defined as a mere physical parameter of each system (e.g., energetic efficiency), without including somehow the relationship/interactions with other systems in the population and with the environment, we consider that such ‘selective dynamics’ is quite far from Darwin’s original idea of evolution by natural selection.

  8. In the context of this article we have in mind complex chemical systems, like self-bounded reaction networks, but a more illustrative example to grasp this idea (that more constraints do not always involve a more reduced dynamic space) consists in the following: a comparison between the complexity of the pieces (components) and rules (dynamic constraints) of chess and draughts, with regard to the richness of the game they can respectively generate on the same board (general physico-chemical scenario).

  9. ‘Fixed’ does not mean unchangeable but temporarily stable, dependable as a recurrent mechanism. In fact, we find the co-evolutionary account of the origins of the present genetic code (Wong 1975; Di Giulio 1989) quite a reasonable and interesting hypothesis.

References

  • Anet FAL (2004) The place of metabolism in the origin of life. Curr Opin Chem Biol 8:654–659

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (2005) Discovering cell mechanisms: the creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner SA (1999) How small can a microorganism be? In: Size limits of very small microorganisms (Proceedings on a workshop). National Academy Press, Washington, D.C., pp 126–135

  • Boogerd F, Bruggeman F, Hofmeyr J, Westerhof H (eds) (2007) Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier, Amsterdam

  • Brooks DR, Wiley EO (1988 [1986]) Evolution as entropy: toward a unified theory of biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Coffman JA (2006) Developmental ascendancy: from bottom-up to top-down control. Biol Theory 1(2):165–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Deamer DW. (1997) The first living systems: a bioenergetic perspective. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 61:239–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Duve C de (1991) Blueprint for a cell: the nature and origin of life. Neil Patterson Publishers, Burlington, North Carolina

    Google Scholar 

  • Duve C de (2005) The onset of selection. Nature 433:581–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dyson FJ (1985) Origins of life. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M (1992) Steps towards life: a perspective on evolution. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M, Schuster P (1979) The hypercycle: a principle of natural self-organization. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferris JP (1994) The prebiotic synthesis and replication of RNA oligomers: the transition from prebiotic molecules to the RNA world. In: Fleischaker GR, Colonia S, Luisi PL (eds) Self-production of supramolecular structures. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 89–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleischaker GR (1994) A few precautionary words concerning terminology. In: Fleischaker GR, Colonia S, Luisi PL (eds) Self-production of supramolecular structures. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 33–41

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontana W (1992) Algorithmic chemistry. In: Langton CG, Taylor C, Farmer JD, Rasmussen S (eds) Artificial life II. Addison-Wesley, Redwood City, pp 159–209

  • Gánti T (1975) Organization of chemical reactions into dividing and metabolizing units: the chemotons. BioSystems 7:15–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gánti T (2003) The principles of life. With a commentary by J. Griesemer and E. Szathmáry. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Giulio M di (1989) Some aspects of the organization and evolution of the genetic code. J Mol Evol 29:191–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer J (2000) The units of evolutionary transition. Selection 1:67–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harold FM (1986) The vital force. A study of bioenergetics. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Harold FM (2001) The way of the cell. Molecules, organisms and the order of life. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1980) Individuality and selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 11:311–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce GF (1989) RNA evolution and the origins of life. Nature 338:217–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampis G (1991) Self-modifying systems in biology and cognitive science: a new framework for dynamics, information and complexity. Pergamon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (1986) Autocatalytic sets of proteins. J Theor Biol 119:1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (1993) The origins of order: self-organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (2000) Investigations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman SA (2003) Molecular autonomous agents. Philos Trans R Soc Lond A 361:1089–1099

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2000) The century of the gene. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA:

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF (2007) The disappearance of function from ‘self organizing’ systems. In: Boogerd F, Bruggeman F, Hofmeyr J, Westerhof H (eds), Systems biology: philosophical foundations. Elsevier B.V

  • Kiedrowski G von (1986) A self-replicating hexadeoxy nucleotide. Angew Chem Int Ed Engl 25:932–935

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1970) The units of selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 1:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi PL (1994) The chemical implementation of autopoiesis. In: Fleischaker GR, Colonia S, Luisi PL (eds) Self-production of supramolecular structures. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, pp 179–197

  • Maturana H, Varela FJ (1973) De Máquinas y Seres Vivos—Una teoría sobre la organización biológica. Editorial Universitaria S.A., Santiago de Chile

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana H, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition. The realization of the living. D. Riedel Publishing Company, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1986) The problems of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. Freeman & Co., Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin B (2000) John von Neumann and the evolutionary growth of complexity: looking backward, looking forward… Artif Life 6:347–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moreno A, Umerez J, Fernández J (1994) Definition of life and research program in artificial life. Ludus Vitalis II(3):15–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno A, Fernández J (1990) Structural limits for evolutive capacities in molecular complex systems. Biol Forum 83(2/3):335–347

    Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz HJ (1968) Energy flow in Biology. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz HJ (1992) Beginnings of cellular life. Yale University Press, Binghamton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz HJ, Heinz B, Deamer DW (1988) The chemical logic of a minimum protocell. Orig Life Evol Biosph 18:281–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehaniv CL (2000) Measuring evolvability as the rate of complexity increase. Artificial life 7 Workshop Proceedings, edited by Carlo C. Maley and Eilis Boudreau, pp 55–57

  • Neumann J von (1948 [1951]) The general and logical theory of automata. In: Cerebral mechanisms in behavior: the Hixon Symposium. John Wiley and Sons Inc, New York

  • Neumann J von (1949 [1966]) Theory of self-reproducing automata. In: Burks AW (ed), University of Illinois, Urbana

  • Nicolis G, Prigogine Y (1977) Self-organization in non-equilibrium systems. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Oparin AI (1961) Life: its nature, origin and development. Oliver and Boyd, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Orgel LE (1992) Molecular replication. Nature 358:203–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1965) The recognition of hereditary order in primitive chemical systems. In: Fox S (ed) The origins of prebiological systems. Academic Press, New York, pp 385–405

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1968) The physical basis of coding and reliability in biological evolution. In: Waddington CH (ed) Towards a theoretical biology 1. Edinburgh University Press, Prolegomena, Edinburgh, pp 67–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1977) Dynamic and linguistic modes of complex systems. Int J Gen Syst 3:259–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1982) Cell psychology: an evolutionary approach to the symbol-matter problem. Cognition Brain Theor 4:325–341

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine I, Stengers I (1979) La nouvelle alliance. Métamorphose de la science. Gallimard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Pross A (2004) Causation and the origin of life. Metabolism or replication first? Orig Life Evol Biosph 34:307–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rocha LM (2001) Evolution with material symbol systems. BioSystems 60:95–121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1973) On the dynamical realizations of (M, R)-systems. Bull Math Biophys 35:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1991) Life itself: a comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin and fabrication of life. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Moreno A (1998) Autonomy and emergence: how systems become agents through the generation of functional constraints. In: Farre GL, Oksala T (eds) Emergence, complexity, hierarchy, organization (Selected and edited papers from the ECHO III Conference), Acta Polytechnica Scandinavica Ma91, 273–282. The Finnish Academy of Technology, Espoo-Helsinki

  • Ruiz-Mirazo K, Moreno A (2004) Basic autonomy as a fundamental step in the synthesis of life. Artif Life 10(3):235–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz -Mirazo K, Peretó J., Moreno A (2004) A universal definition of life: autonomy and open-ended evolution. Orig Life Evol Biosph 34(3):323–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuring I, Czárán T, Szabó P, Károlyi G, Toroczkai Z (2003) Spatial models of prebiotic evolution: soup before pizza?. Orig Life Evol Biosph 33:319–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Science (2002) Special issue—Systems Biology. Science 295:1661–1682

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segré D, Ben-Eli D, Lancet D (2000) Compositional genomes: prebiotic information transfer in mutually catalytic non-covalent assemblies. Proc Natl Acad Sci 97:4112–4117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro R (2000) A replicator was not involved in the origin of life. IUBMB Life 49:173–176

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro R (2002) Monomer world. In: Abstracts of the 13th International Conference on the Origin of Life, 10th ISSOL Meeting, Oaxaca, Mexico, p 60

  • Spiegelman S (1967) An in vitro analysis of a replicating molecule. Am Sci 55:221–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Srere PA (1984) Why are enzymes so big?. Trends Biochem Sci 9:387–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmáry E. (2000) The evolution of replicators. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B 355:1669–1676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmáry E, Maynard Smith J (1997) From replicators to reproducers: the first major transitions leading to life. J Theor Biol 187:555–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmáry E, Santos M, Fernando C (2005) Evolutionary potential and requirements for minimal protocells. Top Curr Chem 259:167–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szathmáry E. (2006) The origins of replicators and reproducers. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B 361:1761–1776

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor T (1999) From artificial evolution to artificial life. Ph. D. Dissertation. University of Edinburgh

  • Umerez J (1998) The evolution of the symbolic domain in living systems and artificial life. In: van de Vijver G, Salthe S, Delpos M (eds) Evolutionary systems. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 377–396

    Google Scholar 

  • Umerez J (2001) Howard Pattee’s theoretical biology: a radical epistemological stance to approach life, evolution and complexity. BioSystems 60:159–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff H, Palsson B (2004) The evolution of molecular biology into systems biology. Nat Biotechnol 22(10):1249–1252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wächtershäuser W (1990) Evolution of the first metabolic cycles. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 87:200–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber BH, Depew DJ, Smith JD (eds) (1988) Entropy, information, and evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicken JS (1987) Evolution, thermodynamics and information. Extending the darwinian program. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong JT (1975) A co-evolution theory of the genetic code. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 72:1909–1912

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woese C (2002) On the evolution of cells. Proc Natl Acad Sci 99(13):8742–8747

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Kepa Ruiz-Mirazo carried out this research work thanks to a post-doctoral fellowship from the Basque Government and became a Ramon y Cajal fellow in the course of it. Jon Umerez was also a Ramon y Cajal fellow during most of the time required for the elaboration of the article. We thank the editor, Kim Sterelny, and an anonymous reviewer for useful criticism on previous versions of this manuscript. We would also like to acknowledge financial help from research grants 9/UPV 00003.230-15840/2004, HUM2005-02449 and BMC2003-06957.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kepa Ruiz-Mirazo.

Glossary (of specific chemical terms)

Glossary (of specific chemical terms)

Work (thermodynamic definition): any form of energy that, unlike heat, can be kept and used by a system without dispersion.

Exergonic process: A process defined by a decrease in the system’s Gibbs free energy (ΔG < 0, at constant pressure and temperature), so it is thermodynamically spontaneous. This involves the release of energy, originally in the form of work, to the surroundings.

Endergonic process: A process defined by an increase in the system’s Gibbs free energy (ΔG > 0, at constant pressure and temperature), so it is thermodynamically non-spontaneous. This involves the absorption of energy, in the form of work, from the surroundings.

Endergonic–exergonic coupling: the coming together (in time and space) of two processes, one endergonic and one exergonic, so that the former (non-spontaneous in normal circumstances) takes place at the expense of the latter. The release of energy associated to the exergonic process is, thus, constrained, so that it is absorbed by the endergonic one, leading to an overall production of work.

Supramolecular chemistry: term that refers to the area of chemistry which focuses on the non-covalent bonding interactions of molecules (hydrogen bonds, metal coordination, hydrophobic forces, van der Waals forces, pi–pi interactions, electrostatic effects to assemble molecules into multimolecular complexes,…).

Multimers/Oligomers: molecular chains that consist of a finite number of monomer units (a few—up to 10/more than a few—up to 100)

Polymers: molecular chains that consist of a large (unbounded) number of monomer units (more than 100)

Stereochemistry: a sub-discipline of chemistry that involves the study of the relative spatial arrangement of atoms within molecules, including the case of chiral molecules (particularly relevant in biochemistry).

Active site: small pocket on the surface of an enzyme where catalysis actually occurs. The structure and chemical properties of the active site allow the recognition and binding of the substrate(s).

Chemical affinity: tendency of an atom or compound to combine by chemical reaction with atoms or compounds of unlike composition.

Energetic degeneracy: situation in which the different arrangements of the parts within a system are equi-probable, due to the fact that their corresponding energy levels are the same.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ruiz-Mirazo, K., Umerez, J. & Moreno, A. Enabling conditions for ‘open-ended evolution’. Biol Philos 23, 67–85 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9076-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9076-8

Keywords

Navigation