Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Bargaining over a climate deal: deadline and delay

  • Published:
Annals of Operations Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Assuming that a North-South transfer is the key to effective climate cooperation, we ask when and how much the North should offer to the South in return for a commitment to reduce deforestation and forest degradation. In light of the risk of irreversible damage over time, we examine a negotiation with a deadline. In this case, the North threatens the South over a negotiation dead-end in case an agreement is not reached rapidly. We assess the conditions for an agreement to be immediate or delayed, and discuss those situations likely to result in negotiation failure. Despite the risk of irreversible damage over time, we show that cooperation is likely to be delayed and we identify situations wherein the North and South do not reach an agreement within the deadline. Although Pareto-improving, cooperation may collapse because of inefficiencies related to incomplete information. What’s more, we show that in negotiations with a deadline, uncertainty about the benefits deriving from cooperation and the irreversibility of the damage that will be caused if cooperation is delayed are the two key components affecting choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These documents are available on the official United Nations website dedicated to the REDD mechanism, see www.un-redd.org.

  2. http://www.nationalcenter.org/KyotoSenate.html.

  3. Exhaustive surveys of this literature can be found in Finus (2008) and Jørgensen et al. (2010).

  4. Several newspaper articles referred to this threat. Refer to articles entitled “As threat grows, UN talks face failure” ( Sydney Morning Herald, 8 of August 2010), “Why failure of climate summit would herald global catastrophe: 3.5C” (The Independent, 31 of August 2010 ) or “Copenhagen climate deal: Spectacular failure—or a few important steps?” published December the 22nd, 2009 in the Guardian.

  5. Note that we use the term coalition to be consistent with the terminology used in the literature. In this paper, coalitions cannot split and the term refers to a group of countries.

  6. They look for an equilibrium that is the limit of finite-horizon equilibria. In other words, they explicitly compute a sequence of finite-horizon equilibria in a simple case and derive a limit.

  7. Rubinstein (1985) imposes some monotonicity conditions on off-the-equilibrium-path conjectures in order to obtain a sequential equilibrium.

  8. Note that sticking points are more about historical deforestation baselines and implementation matters. In other words, the South bargains about how to share the “pie” rather than about the size of the “pie” itself.

  9. For readability purpose, in some following equations we abuse notations and write p 2 instead of \(p_{2}^{{}}(\tau _{1})\).

  10. For an exhaustive discussion refer to Camerer (2003).

  11. In the case of a mixed action, μ 2(X S c,τ 2), the probability distribution over X S is conditional on the minimum acceptable transfer level and the amount offered.

  12. Irreversible damage is likely to be the principal factor in depreciation, before discounting, the period of time we consider being relatively small.

  13. Note that with the specification of the utility functions considered in the paper, the irreversible damage that will occur over time in the South is always supported by the North. This damage might also possibly make South more likely to join the agreement at a lower price in the second period, which would translate into the same model but with the addition, rather than subtraction of α S in the utility function of the South. In this case, the North does not support the damage in the South but substracts it from its second period offer. If α N +α S remains positive, all our results are robust. Otherwise, there is a threshold to α N +α S such that North will offer \(\widehat{\tau }\) at the first period if it is soft, and c if it is hard. In other words, the North will make lower offers in the first period and the South will have an incentive to accept them. In this situation there will still be a positive probability that negotiations will succeed and a positive probability that they will fail.

References

  • Andreoni, J., & Blanchard, E. (2006). Testing subgame perfection apart from fairness in ultimatum games. Experimental Economics, 9, 307–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, S. (2001). International cooperation for sale. European Economic Review, 45, 1835–1850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F. (2003). Behavioral game theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caparros, A., Péreau, J. C., & Tazdaït, T. (2004). North-South climate change negotiations: a sequential game with asymmetric information. Public Choice, 121, 455–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carraro, C., & Siniscalco, D. (1993). Strategies for the international protection of the environment. Journal of Public Economics, 52, 309–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chander, P., & Tulkens, H. (1995). A core-theoretic for the design of cooperative agreements on transfrontier pollution. International Tax and Public Finance, 2, 279–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chander, P., & Tulkens, H. (1997). The core of an economy with multilateral environmental externalities. International Journal of Game Theory, 26, 379–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Compte, O., & Jehiel, P. (1995). On the role of arbitration in negotiations. Mimeo, CERAS – ENPC.

  • Deplege, J. (2005). The organization of global negotiations: constructing the climate change regime. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eyckmans, J., & Finus, M. (2009). An almost ideal sharing scheme for coalition games with externalities. Stirling Discussion paper series, 2009-10, University of Stirling.

  • Finus, M. (2008). Game-theoretic research on the design of international environmental agreements: insights, critical remarks and future challenges. International Review of Environmental and Resource Economics, 2, 29–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., & Tirole, J. (1983). Sequential bargaining with incomplete information. Review of Economic Studies, 50, 221–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuentes-Albero, C., & Rubio, S. (2010). Can international environmental cooperation be bought. European Journal of Operational Research, 202, 255–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gneezy, U., Haruvy, E., & Roth, A. (2003). Bargaining under a deadline: evidence from the reverse ultimatum game. Games and Economic Behavior, 45, 347–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jørgensen, S., Martín-Herrán, G., & Zaccour, D. (2010). Dynamic games in the economics and management of pollution. Environmental Modeling & Assessment, 15, 433–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., & Mariotti, M. (2001). Perfect equilibria in a model of bargaining with arbitration. Games and Economic Behavior, 37, 170–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., & Ponsati, C. (2006). Stackeholder bargaining games. International Journal of Game Theory, 34, 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parry, M., Canziani, O., Palutikoff, J., van der Linden, P., & Hanson, C. (2007). Impacts, adaptation and vulnerability: contribution of working group II to the fourth assessment report of the IPCC. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ponsati, C. (2004). Economic diplomacy. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 6, 675–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapoport, A., Weig, D., & Felsenthal, D. (1990). Effects of fixed costs in two-person sequential bargaining. Theory and Decision, 28, 47–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapoport, A., Erev, I., & Zwick, R. (1995). An experimental study of buyer-seller negotiation with one-sided incomplete information and time discounting. Management Science, 41, 377–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rotillon, G., Tazdaït, T., & Zeghni, S. (1996). Bilateral or multilateral bargaining in the face of global environmental change. Ecological Economics, 18, 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (1982). Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica, 50, 97–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. (1985). Choice of conjectures in a bargaining game with incomplete information. In A. E. Roth (Ed.), Game-theoretic models of bargaining (pp. 99–114). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, J., & Takahashi, I. (1983). A multi-stage model of bargaining. Review of Economic Studies, 50, 411–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulkens, H. (1998). Cooperation vs. free riding in international environmental affairs: two approaches. In Hanley, N., & Folmer, H. (eds.), Game theory and the environment (pp. 30–44). London: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN-REDD (2011). About UN-REDD programme and about REDD+, Documents available online, www.un-redd.org.

  • Weg, E., & Zwick, R. (1991). On the robustness of perfect equilibrium in fixed cost sequential bargaining under isomorphic transformation. Economics Letters, 36, 21–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weikard, H. P. (2009). Cartel stability under optimal sharing rule. Manchester School, 77, 575–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, C. A. (2001). Mediation and the Nash bargaining solution. Review of Economic Design, 6, 353–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Francis Bloch, Minh Ha Duong, Raphaël Soubeyran and Sylvie Thoron for their helpful comments on previous versions of this paper. The participants of the 11th Annual Conference on Public Economic Theory (Istanbul, 2010) and of the 13th Annual BIOECON Conference (Geneva, 2011), together with two anonymous referees are also gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Courtois.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Propositions 2 and 3

Because they are related, we present a common proof for Propositions 2 and 3. This proof proceeds in two steps.

Step 1. We start by characterizing the best response strategies and study the three cases: when τ 1 < \(\widehat{\tau }\), when \(\widehat{\tau }\leq \tau _{1}\) < c + and when τ 1=c +.

Case 1. If τ 1=c +, any type of South accepts the offer in the first period, an agreement is immediately reached, and the North obtains Bc +.

Case 2. If \(\widehat{\tau }\leq \tau _{1}\) < c +, a coalition S always accepts the offer in the first period, μ 1(ac ,τ 1)=1, and a coalition S + always rejects it, μ 1(ac +,τ 1)=0. In case that the South rejects the offer in the first period, the North knows with certainty that the South is a coalition S + and therefore offers a transfer c ++α S in the second period, which is always accepted. The payoff for the North then is \(p_{1}^{-}(B-\tau _{1})+p_{1}^{+}\delta (B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})\) and is maximum when \(\tau _{1}=\widehat{\tau }\).

Case 3. If c τ 1 < \(\widehat{\tau }\), coalition S + always rejects the offer in the first period, μ 1(ac +,τ 1)=0. Let χ be the value of μ 1(ac ,τ 1) such that the North is indifferent between offering c ++α S and c +α S in the second period when μ 1(ac +,τ 1)=0.

The North updates its beliefs in the second period over the type of S. We have:

For the North to be indifferent between offers c ++α S and c +α S in the second period, χ should be such that \(\frac{(1-\chi )p_{1}^{-}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})+\frac{p_{1}^{+}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})=\frac{(1-\chi )p_{1}^{-}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})\) and therefore we have:

$$\chi =1-\frac{p_{1}^{+}(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})}{p_{1}^{-}(c^{+}-c^{-})}$$

We can prove now that in this case, a S coalition always adopts the mixed strategy χ in the first period.

First, note that if the North offers τ 2(τ 1)=c ++α S , its expected payoff in the second period is \(p_{2}^{-}(\tau _{1})(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})+p_{2}^{+}(\tau _{1})(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})=B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S}\). If it offers τ 2(τ 1)=c +α S , its expected payoff is \(p_{2}^{-}(\tau _{1})(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})=(1-p_{2}^{+}(\tau _{1}))(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})\).

We can deduce that the North adopts c ++α S with probability 1 in the second period only if \(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S}>p_{2}^{-}(\tau _{1})(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})\) and therefore if μ 1(ac ,τ 1)>χ. The North adopts c +α S with probability 1 in the second period only if μ 1(ac ,τ 1)<χ and adopts a mixed strategy which we denote as [1−σ 2(τ 1),σ 2(τ 1)] offering c ++α S with probability σ 2(τ 1) if μ 1(ac ,τ 1)=χ.

Second, note that if the North offers c ++α S in the second period, a coalition S anticipates it and rejects any first period offer strictly lower than \(\widehat{\tau }\). It follows that \(\tau _{1}\in [ c^{-},\widehat{\tau }[ \), μ 1(ac ,τ 1)=0, which contradicts the previous statement. Similarly, if coalition S anticipates that the North will offer c +α S in the second period, it should accept any offers \(\tau _{1}\in [ c^{-},\widehat{\tau }[\) in the first period, which also contradicts the first statement. We can deduce that the only feasible alternative is that a coalition S always adopts a mixed strategy χ in the first period which fulfils our claim.

Given that a S coalition plays a mixed strategy χ∈]0,1[ in the first period, χ is such that the expected payoff from accepting or rejecting offer τ 1 is the same. We then have: τ 1c =δ(1−σ 2(τ 1))(c +α S c α S )+δσ 2(τ 1)(c ++α S c α S ) and, therefore:

$$\sigma _{2}(\tau _{1})=\frac{\tau _{1}-c^{-}}{\delta (c^{+}-c^{-})}.$$

The expected payoff to the North associated with χ is \(p_{1}^{-}\chi (B-\tau _{1})+p_{1}^{-}\frac{(1-\chi )p_{1}^{-}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}\delta (B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})\) which is at a maximum when τ 1=c . We can deduce that given that the North offers c in the first period, it never offers c ++α S in the second period because σ 2(τ 1)=0. The offer in the second period is τ 2(τ 1)=c +α S . At equilibrium, the North offers τ 1=c and τ 2=c +α S . A coalition S accepts the offer with probability χ in the first period and always accepts the offer in the second, while a coalition S + always rejects the offer. The expected payoff for the North is then \(p_{1}^{-}\chi (B-c^{-})+p_{1}^{-}\frac{(1-\chi )p_{1}^{-}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}\delta (B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})\).

Step 2. Next we study the first period offer, that is the conditions for the North to offer \(c^{-},\widehat{\tau }\) or c +. We can deduce from proposition 1 that the North prefers to offer \(\widehat{\tau }\) rather than c + as soon as c +> \(\overline{c^{+}}\). We start by proving that if W<c +< \(\overline{c^{+}}\), the North offers \(\widehat{\tau }\) or c rather than c +. Consider the mapping g:ℝ→ℝ with

$$g(\delta )=\Pi _{H}-\Pi _{L}=B-c^{+}-p_{1}^{-}\chi (B-c^{-})-p_{1}^{-}\frac{(1-\chi )p_{1}^{-}}{1-\chi p_{1}^{-}}\delta (B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})$$

and where Π H and Π L respectively denote the North’s payoffs when the first period offer is high or low. Note that g(δ) is decreasing in δ and g(δ)=0 when \(\delta =\overline{\delta }=\frac{(1-\chi p_{1}^{-})[c^{+}-\chi p_{1}^{-}c^{-}-(1-\chi p_{1}^{-})B]}{(p_{1}^{-})^{2}(\chi -1)(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{-}-\alpha _{S})}\). Given \(\chi =1-\frac{p_{1}^{+}(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})}{p_{1}^{-}(c^{+}-c^{-})}\), note that \(\overline{\delta }\leq 0\) if and only if \(c^{+}-\chi p_{1}^{-}c^{-}-(1-\chi p_{1}^{-})B\geq 0\), which is always true. We can deduce that \(\overline{\delta }\) is always negative, and it follows that for any admissible δ∈[0,1], g(δ)<0 and the North always prefers the strategy (c ,c +α S ) to strategy (c +,c ++α S ). The North never makes a high offer at the first period.

Next, we show that the choice for the North to play either \(\widehat{\tau }\) or c relies on the degradation of benefits over time. Define the mapping Δ:ℝ→ℝ with Δ=Π M −Π L and notice that Δ=0 when \(\delta =\widetilde{\delta }=\frac{p_{1}^{+}(B-c^{-})(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})}{(c^{-}-c^{+})Z}\) with \(Z=(2p_{1}^{+}-1)(B-\alpha _{N}-c^{+}-\alpha _{S})+(1-p_{1}^{+})(c^{-}-c^{+})\) and \(\widetilde{\delta }\leq 1\). Define ε∈ℝ such that δ= \(\widetilde{\delta }+\varepsilon \) and note that Δ=. We now consider the two cases where \(p_{1}^{+}\gtrless 1/2\).

First, consider the case where \(p_{1}^{+}<1/2\) and note that in this case \(\widetilde{\delta }>0\) because Z<0. We can deduce that Δ is positive when ε<0 and negative when ε>0. The median offer is chosen as soon as \(\delta <\widetilde{\delta }\).

Second, consider the case where \(p_{1}^{+}>1/2\), a priori Z can either be positive or negative. We can prove that given c +>W. Note that given \(p_{1}^{+}>1/2\), Z is decreasing in c + and Z=0 when \(c^{+}=\widetilde{c}=\) \(\frac{(2p_{1}^{+}-1)(B-\alpha _{N}-\alpha _{S})+(1-p_{1}^{+})c^{-}}{p_{1}^{+}}\). \(\widetilde{c}<W\) as soon as \(\alpha _{N}+\alpha _{S}>\frac{(1-p_{1}^{+})^{2}(B-c^{-})}{1-2p_{1}^{+}}\), which is always true since by assumption, α N +α S ≥0 and \(p_{1}^{+}>1/2\). We can deduce that \(c^{+}>\widetilde{c}\) and therefore Z<0. We conclude that Δ is also positive as soon as \(\delta <\widetilde{\delta }\), which completes the proof. □

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Courtois, P., Tazdaït, T. Bargaining over a climate deal: deadline and delay. Ann Oper Res 220, 205–221 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-011-1018-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10479-011-1018-9

Keywords

Navigation