Skip to main content
Log in

Welfare egalitarianism with other-regarding preferences

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider the problem of dividing a perfectly divisible good among individuals who have other-regarding preferences. Assuming no legitimate claims and purely ordinal preferences, how should society measure social welfare so as to satisfy basic principles of efficiency and fairness? In a simple model of average externalities, we characterize the class of social preferences which give full priority to the individual with the lowest egalitarian equivalent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The small existing literature on fairness and externalities focuses on allocation rules (Villar 1988; Nieto 1991; Kolm 1995; Velez 2016). Only Decerf and Van der Linden (2016) follow the same approach as this paper. They investigate the problem of defining fair social orderings for the allocation of multiple goods on a domain of preferences that exclude altruistic preferences. However, their more general framework does not allow for characterization results.

  2. Defining such a comprehensive measure of social welfare is essential when the subset of feasible allocations is limited or uncertain, which may happen in particular if the social planner has to respect different types of legal, political or informational constraints. The approach has been applied to many different issues, including the fair allocation of multiple divisible goods (Fleurbaey 2005, 2007; Fleurbaey and Maniquet 2008), public goods ( Maniquet and Sprumont 2004, 2005) or indivisible goods (Maniquet 2008). It has also been used for the evaluation of income tax schedules (Fleurbaey and Maniquet 2006) and the comparison of allocations for populations of different sizes and preferences (Fleurbaey and Tadenuma 2014).

  3. Throughout the paper we use the term consumption to refer to the amount allocated to each individual.

  4. A weaker requirement would be that for any allocation x in \(\mathbb {R}_{+}^N\), and any \(\delta \in ]0,x_i]\), there exists \(\lambda >\frac{\delta }{n-1}\) such that \(\displaystyle { x\;P_i\;\left( x_i-\delta ,(x_j + \lambda )_{j\ne i}\right) }\). When combined with all of our other requirements, this weaker axiom allows for indifference curves (see description of the consumption space below) with a slope in \(]0,\frac{n-2}{n}]\), which are forbidden under the original axiom. While we believe that a similar characterization result as Theorem 1 could be obtained with that weaker version of Bounded Altruism, we stick to the original version for simplicity.

  5. Alternatively, we could assume individuals care about the average consumption in the rest of the economy \(\bar{x}_{-i}=\sum _{k \ne i} x_k \slash (n-1)\). While the two assumptions are formally equivalent (they define the same subdomain of preferences), the choice of focusing on the average consumption is not totally innocuous as the axioms and properties we impose (which refer to the average consumption) would have different implications if they were to refer instead to the average consumption in the rest of the economy \(\bar{x}_{-i}\).

  6. We also abuse notation by sometimes comparing allocations \(x\in \mathbb {R}_+^N\) with bundles \((x_i,\bar{x})\in \mathbb {R}_{+}^2\).

  7. See the appendix for a formal definition of these two monotonicity properties and a proof of the implications.

  8. Note, however, that on \(\mathcal {R}_A\), if the egalitarian equivalent exists then it is necessarily unique.

  9. Note that because of Preference for Positive Consumption and Continuity, the vertical axis must necessarily constitute an indifference curve.

  10. Assume, by contradiction, that there exists two allocations x and y such that \(\bar{x}<\bar{y}\) and x Pareto dominates y. Let i be any individual in N. Then, because i must necessarily prefer x to y, Uniform Monotonicity means that \(y_i<x_i+(\bar{y}-\bar{x})\). However, this also implies that there exists at least one other individual j for which \(y_j>x_j+(\bar{y}-\bar{x})\). By Uniform Monotonicity again, j must prefer (strictly) y to x, a contradiction since x Pareto dominates y. For the same reason, two different allocations are never Pareto indifferent on \(\mathcal {R}_A\).

  11. The standard Pigou-Dalton transfer principle used in the theory of inequality measurement (Pigou 1912) requires any transfer from some richer to some poorer individual (while preserving their relative order) to be considered a social improvement. It reflects a stronger form of resource egalitarianism than Transfer to Disadvantaged because it also applies to pairs of individuals who are either both advantaged or both disadvantaged. Note that in contrast with the classical setting, Transfer and Pareto are compatible on \(\mathcal {R}_A\). Consider for example R(.) such that \(xR(R_N)y\) iff \(\min _{i\in N}x_i+\bar{x}\ge \min _{i\in N}y_i+\bar{y}\).

  12. In social choice, this requirement is generally referred to as Independence from Indifferent Individuals (Sen 1970).

  13. In Fleurbaey (2007) the fairness requirement takes the form of a mean support dominance property, while in Fleurbaey and Maniquet 2011 (Fleurbaey and Maniquet 2011) a combination of two transfer principles.

  14. Consider for example \(x\,{R}(R_N)\,y\) iff \(\bar{x}\ge \bar{y}\).

  15. In the classical multi-dimensional setting, the closest axiom to Transfer to Disadvantaged would be Equal Split Transfer. Combining Strong Pareto, Unchange-Contour Independence and Equal-Split Transfer leads to Equal Split Priority (Fleurbaey and Maniquet 2011).

  16. Whereby \(\min _N u_i(x,R_i)=\min _N u_i(y,R_i)\) implies \(x\;I(R_N)\;y\).

  17. Other social ordering functions also satisfy all the requirements. One such example, as suggested in Fleurbaey and Maniquet (2011) (for a different context), consists in applying a different leximin social ordering to break possible ties in the original leximin social ordering function.

  18. Where \(U_j(x,R_j)\) denotes the upper contour set of preference relation \(R_j\) at j’s consumption bundle \((x_j,\bar{x})\).

  19. Otherwise, let \(B=\{i\in N \mid x_i\le \bar{x}\}\), \(a>\bar{x}\), and define allocation \(\tilde{x}\) such that:

    $$\begin{aligned}&\tilde{x}_i=q_i(x,a,R_i) \;\;\forall i\in B\\&\tilde{x}_i=x_i+(a-\bar{x})+\frac{1}{n-\#B}\left( \sum _{j\in B}x_j+(a-\bar{x})-\tilde{x}_j\right) \;\;\forall i\not \in B \end{aligned}$$

    Note that \(\bar{\tilde{x}}=a\) and \(\tilde{x}_i\ne \bar{\tilde{x}}\) for all \(i\in N\). Since \(\tilde{x} I_i x\) for all \(i\in B\), Uniform Monotonicity implies \(x_i+(a-\bar{x})>\tilde{x}_i\) for all \(i\in B\). Therefore, \(\tilde{x}_i>x_i+(a-\bar{x})\) for all \(i\not \in B\), which by Uniform Monotonicity again, implies that \(\tilde{x} P_i x\) for all \(i\not \in B\). By Strong Pareto, we get that \(\tilde{x}P(R_N)x\). Since \(\min _{i\in N}u_i(\hat{x})=\min _{i\in N}u_i(x)<\min _{i\in N}u_i(y)\), and \(\tilde{x}_i\ne \bar{\tilde{x}}\) for all \(i\in N\), we can apply the proof of Theorem 1 (see below) to allocations \(\tilde{x}\) and y, which yields \(yP(R_N)\tilde{x}\). This finally implies \(yP(R_N)x\).

  20. In all the figures below individual 3 refers to individual n in the proof.

References

  • Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2000) ERC: a theory of equity, reciprocity, and competition. Am Econ Rev 90(1):166–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness G, Rabin M (2002) Understanding social preferences with simple tests. Q J Econ 117:817–869

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark AE, Frijters P, Shields MA (2008) Relative income, happiness, and utility: An explanation for the Easterlin paradox and other puzzles. J Econ Lit 46:95–144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decerf B, Van der Linden M (2016) Fair social orderings with other-regarding preferences. Soc Choice Welf 46(3):655–694

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duesenberry J (1949) Income, saving, and the theory of consumer behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin R (1995) Will raising the incomes of all increase the happiness of all? J Econ Behav Organ 27:35–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schmidt KM (1999) A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. Q J Econ 114:817–868

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M (2005) The Pazner-*Schmeidler social ordering: a defense. Rev Econ Design 9:145–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M (2007) Two criterias for social decisions. J Econ Theory 134:421–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M (2012) The importance of what people care about. Politics Philos Econ 11(4):415–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2008) Fair social orderings. Econ Theor 34:25–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2006) Fair Income Tax. Rev Econ Stud 73:55–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Maniquet F (2011) A theory of fairness and social welfare, econometric society monograph. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Schokkaert E (2013) Behavioral Welfare Economics and Redistribution. Am Econ J Microecon 5(3):180–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Tadenuma K (2014) Universal social orderings: an integrated theory of policy evaluation, inter-society comparisons, and interpersonal comparisons. Rev Econ Stud 81:1071–1101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Trannoy A (2003) The impossibility of a Paretian Egalitarian. Soc Choice Welf 21:243–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank RH (1985) Positional externalities cause large and preventable welfare losses. Am Econ Rev 95(2):137–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank RH (2005) Choosing the right pond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaertner W (2006) A primer in social choice theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath J (2006) Envy and Efficiency. Revue de philosophie économique 14:3–30

  • Kolm SC (1995) The economics of social sentiments: the case of envy. Jpn Econ Rev 46:63–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maniquet F (2008) Social orderings for the assignment of indivisible objects. J Econ Theory 143(1):199–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maniquet F, Sprumont Y (2004) Fair production and allocation of an excludable nonrival good. Econometrica 72(2):627–640

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maniquet F, Sprumont Y (2005) Welfare egalitarianism in non-rival environments. J Econ Theory 120:155–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1992) Welfare bounds in the cooperative production problem. Games Econ Behav 4:373–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nieto J (1991) A note on Egalitarian and efficient allocations with externalities in consumption. J Public Econ 46:261–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pazner E, Schmeidler D (1978) Egalitarian equivalent allocations: a new concept of economic equity. Q J Econ 92:671–687

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigou AC (1912) Wealth and welfare. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden Day, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel J (2005) Interdependent preferences and reciprocity. J Econ Lit 43(392):436

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprumont Y (2012) Resource Egalitarianism with a dash of efficiency. J Econ Theory 147(1602):1613

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2010) Fair allocation rules. In: Arrow K, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare volume II. North-Holland, Amsterdam, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Varian H (1974) Efficiency, equity and envy. J Econ Theory 9:63–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen T (1899) The theory of the leisure class. MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Velez R (2016) Fairness with externalities. Theor Econ 11:381–410

  • Villar A (1988) On the existence of pareto optimal allocations when individual welfare depends on relative consumption. J Public Econ 36:387–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafael Treibich.

Additional information

I am grateful to Marc Fleurbaey and Jean-François Laslier for their advice and suggestions, as well as two anonymous referees and the associate editor for very helpful remarks. I would also like to thank Benoit Decerf, Yukio Koriyama, Antonin Macé, François Maniquet, Stefan Napel, Lars Peter Østerdal, Eduardo Perez, Paolo Piacquadio, Yves Sprumont, Karol Szwagrzak, Giacomo Valletta and Martin Van der Linden.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Treibich, R. Welfare egalitarianism with other-regarding preferences. Soc Choice Welf 52, 1–28 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1135-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1135-3

Navigation