Skip to main content
Log in

A note on welfarist versus non-welfarist social welfare function

  • Published:
International Tax and Public Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this short paper, we build a simple model where a non-welfarist social welfare function can be transformed into and thus be identical to a welfarist social welfare function in form. Our analysis first suggests that non-welfarist methods of policy assessment can also obey the Pareto principle. More broadly, our analysis is a useful input in thinking rigorously about the formal underpinnings of standard welfare economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Their article has far-reaching implications for many academic fields (e.g., economics, law, philosophy, ethics, political science, and public policy) and people (e.g., economists, legal experts, philosophers, ethicists, political scientists, and policymakers). See, e.g., the relevant discussion in Suzumura (2011).

  2. Fleurbaey et al. (2003) probably have reached the same conclusion that the assertion made by Kaplow and Shavell (2001) is false by stating that “welfarism and the Pareto indifference condition are equivalent” is false because “no Pareto condition by itself entails welfarism” (p. 1383). Our argument is clearly different from theirs. Specifically, Fluerbaey et al. (2003) argued that the assertion made by Kaplow and Shavell (2001) does not hold in the multi-profile approach to normative issues, while we show that it is false even in the single-profile approach to normative issues as assumed by Kaplow and Shavell (2001). Therefore, our critique is more direct and more on the point.

  3. The “observation” made by Kaplow and Shavell (2001) on p.283 says that “A social welfare function \(F\) is not individualistic if and only if there exist \(x,\hspace{0.33em}x{\prime}\in X\) such that \({U}_{i}\left(x\right)={U}_{i}\left(x{\prime}\right)\) for all \(i\) and \(F\left(x\right)\ne F\left(x{\prime}\right)\).” It is important to note that Kaplow and Shavell (2001) did not prove that their “observation” is true, but simply said that “The reader may verify that the following statement is true” (p. 283). We show that their “observation” is false.

  4. Note that Aronsson and Johansson-Stenman (2018) have explored alternative comparison forms and measures of reference consumption and identified several cases where the marginal tax rules are identical between welfarist and non-welfarist governments. We think these cases are special, as suggested by the other studies cited herein.

References

  • An, Z. (2015). On the sufficiency of using the elasticity of taxable income to calculate deadweight loss: The implications of charitable giving and warm glow. International Tax and Public Finance, 22(6), 1040–1047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • An, Z. (2017). When preferences differ: ETI insufficient to calculate DWL. Tax Notes, 155(6), 825–827.

    Google Scholar 

  • An, Z. (2023) On the marginal cost of public funds: The implications of charitable giving and warm glow. IMF Working Paper

  • An, Z., & Coady, D. (2022). Social versus individual work preferences: Implications for optimal income taxation. FinanzArchiv/Public Finance Analysis, 78(4), 393–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aronsson, T., & Johansson-Stenman, O. (2018). Paternalism against Veblen: Optimal taxation and non-respected preferences for social comparisons. American Economic Journal: Economic Policy, 10(1), 39–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, A. B. (2009). Economics as a moral science. Economica, 76(s1), 791–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, A. (1938). A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 52(2), 310–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besley, T. (1988). A simple model for merit good arguments. Journal of Public Economics, 35(3), 371–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blomquist, S., & Micheletto, L. (2006). Optimal redistributive taxation when government’s and agents’ preferences differ. Journal of Public Economics, 90(6–7), 1215–1233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boskin, M. J., & Sheshinski, E. (1978). Optimal redistributive taxation when individual welfare depends upon relative income. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 92(4), 589–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chetty, R. (2009). Is the taxable income elasticity sufficient to calculate deadweight loss? The implications of evasion and avoidance. American Economic Journal: Economic Policy, 1(2), 31–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P. (2006). Optimal tax treatment of private contributions for public goods with and without warm glow preferences. Journal of Public Economics, 90(4–5), 897–919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duesenberry, J. (1949). Income, saving and the theory of consumer. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldstein, M. (1999). Tax avoidance and the deadweight loss of the income tax. Review of Economics and Statistics, 81(4), 674–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., Tungodden, B., & Chang, H. F. (2003). Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle: a comment. Journal of Political Economy, 111(6), 1382–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanbur, R., Keen, M., & Tuomala, M. (1994). Optimal non-linear income taxation for the alleviation of income-poverty. European Economic Review, 38(8), 1613–1632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplow, L., & Shavell, S. (2001). Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle. Journal of Political Economy, 109(2), 281–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirrlees, J. A. (1971). An exploration in the theory of optimal income taxation. Review of Economic Studies, 38(2), 175–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, R. A. (1959). The theory of public finance. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ng, Y. (1987). Relative-income effects and the appropriate level of public expenditure. Oxford Economic Papers, 39(2), 293–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oswald, A. J. (1983). Altruism, jealousy and the theory of optimal non-linear taxation. Journal of Public Economics, 20(1), 77–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. (1947). Foundations of economic analysis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandmo, A. (1983). Ex post welfare economics and the theory of merit goods. Economica, 50(197), 19–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seade, J. (1980). Optimal non-linear policies for non-utilitarian motives. In D. Collard, R. Lecomber, & M. Slater (Eds.), Income distribution: The limits to redistribution. John Wright and Sons: Bristol.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suzumura, K. (2011). Welfarism, individual rights, and procedural fairness. In K. J. Arrow, A. Sen, & K. Suzumura (Eds.), Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare (Vol. 2, pp. 605–685). North-Holland: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tobin, J. (1970). On Limiting the domain of inequality. Journal of Law & Economics, 13(2), 263–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen, T. (1899). The theory of the leisure class. New York: Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinzierl, M. (2014). The promise of positive optimal taxation: normative diversity and a role for equal sacrifice. Journal of Public Economics, 118, 128–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

The views expressed herein are those of the author and do not necessarily represent the views of the IMF, its Executive Board, or IMF management. The author would like to thank Alan J. Auerbach, Ronald B. Davies (the editor of this journal), Feila Zhang, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Zhiyong An made all the contribution to this paper.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zhiyong An.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

An, Z. A note on welfarist versus non-welfarist social welfare function. Int Tax Public Finance (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-023-09790-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-023-09790-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation