Skip to main content
Log in

Social choice correspondences with infinitely many agents: serial dictatorship

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study social choice correspondences (SCC) assigning a set of choices to each pair consisting of a nonempty subset of the set of alternatives and a weak preference profile. The SCC satisfies unanimity if when there is a weakly Pareto dominant alternative, the SCC selects this alternative. Stability requires that the SCC is unaffected by withdrawal of losing alternatives. Independence implies that the SCC selects the same outcome from a subset of the set of alternatives for two preference profiles that are the same on this set. We characterize the SCC satisfying the three axioms, when the set of alternatives is finite but includes more than three alternatives, and the set of agents can have any cardinality. We show that the SCC is a serial dictatorship à la Eraslan and McLennan (J Econ Theory 117:29–54, 2004) and that a serial dictatorship can include “invisible serial dictators” à la Kirman and Sondermann (J Econ Theory 5:267–277, 1972).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cato (2013b) calls our unanimity condition strong Pareto.

  2. Some serial dictatorship results are also found in Campbell and Kelly (2002) Example 3.12, 3.13 in pp. 51–52, Gevers (1979), Dutta et al. (2001) and Grether and Plott (1982).

  3. The Appendix of Hurd and Loeb (1985) provides some important facts concerning ultrafilters. For discussions of ultrafilters in social choice, see Monjardet (1983).

  4. Because we use their result in our proof of Theorem 1, after introducing technical terms, we state it as the Ultrafilter Lemma in Appendix I. In contrast with Campbell and Kelly (2000), we use a full domain of weak preferences, and then their Ultrafilter Lemma holds in our setting as proved in Appendix I.

  5. See Footnote 1. In this article, we define strong Pareto of Cato (2013b) as unanimity.

  6. For the classical works, Gibbard (1973); Satterthwaite (1975). Schmeidler and Sonnenschein (1974) also study the relationship between Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite Theorem. For more recent works, Reny (2001); Eliaz (2004); Ubeda (2004); Vohra (2011). Many preceding works (Geanakoplos 2005; Yu 2012; Barberà 1980, 1983; Campbell and Kelly 2002, for a comprehensive survey) provide another proof of Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem in the case of finitely many agents. Technically, to prove our main theorem, we will use the result in Arrow (1959) that under our three axioms, the SCC generates a social welfare function.

  7. These impossibility theorems include Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem (Arrow 1951), the Gibbard–Satterthwaite Theorem (Gibbard 1973; Satterthwaite 1975), the Impossibility theorem under strategic candidacy (Grether and Plott 1982; Dutta et al. 2001; Eraslan and McLennan 2004), and the characterization of game-theoretic solutions implementing only dictatorial social choices by Jackson and Srivastava (1996). It is also known that there is an interconnection between lexicographic preferences and both Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite Theorem (see Fishburn 1975; Mitra and Sen 2014).

  8. Ultrafilters are well-established objects both in mathematics and in social choice theory. For references, see Comfort and Negrepotis (1974) or Bell and Slomson (1969).

  9. Here, we follow the terminology in Eraslan and McLennan (2004) and refer to \(\rho \) as a tie-breaking rule, even though \(\rho \) is not necessarily strict, and there still may exist multiple alternatives in \(\phi ^{\mathscr {U}, \rho }(X,R)\) after applying the “tie-breaking.” Man and Takayama (2013a) call \(\rho \) a tie-breaking preference.

  10. We thank a referee for proposing the current (and more intuitive) definition to us.

  11. In their paper, our stability is called Arrow’s Choice Axiom.

  12. See Section 17 in Halmos (1974).

  13. Hurd and Loeb (1985) provides a concise proof for this result, which is found as Theorem A.8 in page 221.

References

  • Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values. John Wiley & Sons, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1959) Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica 26(102):121–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S (1980) Pivotal voters: a new proof of Arrow’s theorem. Econ Lett 6(1):13–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S (1983) Strategy-proofness and pivotal voters: a direct proof of the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem. Int Econ Rev 24(2):413–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell J, Slomson A (1969) Models and ultraproducts: an introduction. North-Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (1975) Aggregation of preferences. Q J Econ 89(3):456–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2008) Multi-profile intergenerational social choice. Discussion Paper, Université de Montréal, CIREQ

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2009) Decisive coalitions and coherence properties. Discussion Paper, Université de Montréal, CIREQ

  • Campbell D, Kelly J (2000) Weak independence and veto power. Econ Lett 66:183–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell D, Kelly J (2002) Impossibility theorems in the Arrovian framework. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 35–94

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cato S (2011) Social choice without the Pareto principle: a comprehensive analysis. Soc Choice Welf 39(4):869–889

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cato S (2013a) Quasi-decisiveness, quasi-ultrafilter, and social quasi-orderings. Soc Choice Welfare 41(1):169–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cato S (2013b) Social choice, the strong Pareto principle, and conditional decisiveness. Theory Decis 75(4):563–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comfort W, Negrepotis S (1974) The theory of ultrafilter. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Jackson MO, Le Breton M (2001) Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica 69(4):1013–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliaz K (2004) Social aggregators. Soc Choice Welf 22(2):317–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eraslan H, McLennan A (2004) Strategic candidacy for multivalued voting procedures. J Econ Theory 117(1):29–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn P (1970) Arrow’s impossibility theorem: concise proof and infinite voters. J Econ Theory 2:103–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn P (1975) Axioms for lexicographic preferences. Rev Econ Stud 42(3):415–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geanakoplos J (2005) Three brief proofs of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Theory 26(1):211–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gevers L (1979) On interpersonal comparability and social welfare orderings. Econometrica 47(1):75–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41(4):587–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grether DM, Plott CR (1982) Nonbinary social choice: an impossibility theorem. Rev Econ Stud 49(1):143–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halmos P (1974) Naive set theory. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson B (1976) The existence of group preference functions. Public Choice 28(1):89–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurd A, Loeb P (1985) An introduction to nonstandard real analysis. Academic Press Inc, California

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson MO, Srivastava S (1996) A characterization of game-theoretic solutions which lead to impossibility theorems. Rev Econ Stud 63(1):23–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirman AP, Sondermann D (1972) Arrow’s theorem, many agents, and invisible dictators. J Econ Theory 5:267–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Man P, Takayama S (2013a) A unifying impossibility theorem. Econ Theory 54(2):249–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Man P, Takayama S (2013b) A unifying impossibility theorem for compact metric social alternatives space. School of Economics Discussion Paper, 477

  • Mitra M, Sen D (2014) An alternative proof of Fishburn’s axiomatization of lexicographic preferences. Econ Lett 124:168–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monjardet B (1983) On the use of ultrafilters in social choice theory. In: Pattanaik PK, Salles M (eds) Social Choice and Welfare, vol 5. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 73–78

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reny P (2001) Arrow’s theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem: a unified approach. Econ Lett 70(1):99–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodríguez-Álvarez C (2006) Candidate stability and voting correspondences. Soc Choice Welf 27(3):545–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite MA (1975) Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10(2):187–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler D, Sonnenschein H (1974) The possibility of a cheat proof social choice function: a theorem of A. Gibbard and M. Satterthwaite. Northwestern University, Discussion Paper, p. 89

  • Ubeda L (2004) Neutrality in Arrow and other impossibility theorems. Econ Theory 23(1):195–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulam S (1929) Concerning functions of sets. Fund Math 14(1):231–233

    Google Scholar 

  • Vohra RV (2011) Mechanism design: a linear programming approach. Econometric Society Monographs Series. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yu NN (2012) A one-shot proof of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Theory 50(2):523–525

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shino Takayama.

Additional information

We would like to thank Andrew McLennan for continuous discussion and many suggestions to improve this paper. We are also grateful to Simon Grant, Chiaki Hara, Atsushi Kajii, Ali Khan, Jeff Kline, Claudio Mezzetti, John Quah, Satoru Takahashi, Rabee Tourky, anonymous referees, and other participants in the Australasian Economics PhD Workshop, and the Econometric Society Australasian Meeting held in Sydney. We similarly acknowledge the useful suggestions of seminar participants at Kyoto University and the National University of Singapore. Takayama also gratefully acknowledges the hospitality of the Kyoto Institute of Economic Research and the University of British Columbia. All errors remaining are our own.

Appendices

Appendix I

The chain property is formally defined as follows. Denote the set of weak orderings on Y by f(Y), and the set of linear orderings on Y by l(Y). A social welfare function for outcome set X and domain \(\mathcal {P}\) is a function from \(\mathcal {P}\) into the set of complete binary relations on \(\mathcal {X}\). Let \(\mathcal {P}(Y)\) denote the set of profiles \(r \in f(Y)^N\) such that there is some \(R \in \mathcal {P}\) for which \(r = R|_{Y}\). Given the domain \(\mathcal {P}\), we say that a triple \(\{x, y, z\}\) of alternatives is free if either

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {P}(\{x, y, z\}) = f(\{x, y, z\})^N \text { or } l(\{x, y, z\})^N. \end{aligned}$$

We say that the domain \(\mathcal {P}\) has the chain property if \(|\mathcal {X}| \ge 3\) and for every two ordered pairs (xy) and (wz) of alternatives in \(\mathcal {X}\), there exists an integer k and a sequence \(v_1, \ldots , v_k\) such that all of the triples \(\{x, y, v_1\}, \{y, v_1, v_2\}, \{v_1, v_2, v_3\}, \ldots , \{v_k, w, z\}\) are free.

Proof of Lemma 9

The Ultrafilter Lemma of Campbell and Kelly (2002) shows that a domain of an SWF satisfies the chain property and the SWF satisfies unanimity and independence, \(\mathcal {U}_N\) is an ultrafilter. In our environment, because there are finitely many alternatives in \(\mathcal {X}\) and the domain is a full domain, \(\mathcal {R}^{N}\) has the chain property, and by Lemma 8, \(\mathbf {R}\) satisfies the two properties. Thus the Ultrafilter Lemma holds. \(\square \)

Appendix II

The “if” Part Proof of Proposition 4

Suppose that a coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters \(\mathscr {U}\) and a tie-breaking rule \(\rho \) induce a voting procedure V. Let \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\). For all \(A \in \mathcal {A}\), \(T_{K(R)}(A, R) \subset A\) and thus V satisfies feasibility. Further, the unanimity and independence of V follow from the proofs of Lemma 5 and Lemma 6 by replacing X with \(A \in \mathcal {A}\), and \(\phi ^{\mathscr {U}, \rho }\) with V. To show that V is SCS, take \(x \in \mathcal {X}\) and suppose \(V(\mathcal {X},R) \not = \{x\}\). Then there is some \(y \not = x\) such that \(y \in V(\mathcal {X},R) {\setminus } \{x\}\). Then \(y \in T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}, R)\), which implies that there is no \(k = 1, \ldots , K(R)\) and \(z \in \mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x, y\}\) such that \(z \succ _{R, k} y\). Thus, \(y \in T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\}, R)\), and \(y \in V(\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\},R)\).

Conversely, suppose \(y \in V(\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\},R)\). Then \(y \in T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\}, R)\), which implies that there is no \(k = 1, \ldots , K(R)\) and \(z \in \mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\}\) such that \(z \succ _{R, k} y\). Then \(y \in T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}, R) {\setminus } \{x\}\) or \(\{x\} = T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}, R)\). Thus \(y \in V(\mathcal {X},R) {\setminus } \{x\}\) or otherwise, \(\{x\} = V(\mathcal {X},R)\). By the initial assumption, \(V(\mathcal {X},R) \not = \{x\}\) and thus we conclude that \(y \in V(\mathcal {X},R) {\setminus } \{x\}\). Thus, we obtain \(V(\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\},R) = V(\mathcal {X},R) {\setminus } \{x\}\). \(\square \)

Now suppose that a voting procedure V satisfies feasibility, unanimity, IIA and SCS. Our strategy for proving the “only-if” part of Proposition 4 is as follows. For all \(X \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\) and all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\), we define \(\phi \) to be:

$$\begin{aligned} \phi (X, R) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^X), \end{aligned}$$
(14)

where \(R^X\) is the preference profile that takes X to the top from R. We will show that \(\phi \) satisfies unanimity, independence and stability. Then by Theorem 1, a coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters and a tie-breaking rule induce \(\phi \), and \(\phi \) is a serial dictatorship. Then we show that the coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters and tie-breaking rule which induce \(\phi \) also induce V defined in (14).

Fix \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\). The proof of the following lemma, which guarantees that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \subset X\) occupies the rest of the subsection. Eraslan and McLennan (2004) prove a similar result for the case of finite \(\mathcal {N}\) as their Lemma 1 (in pages 41 – 42). A similar logic works in our case, even when the case of infinitely many agents is included.

Lemma 16

If \(x \in V(\mathcal {X},R)\), then x is not strongly Pareto dominated at R.

Lemma 16 implies that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \subset X\) for every \(X \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\). Let \(x \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\). We say that \(R'\) is an x -modification of \(R\) if \(R|_{\mathcal {X}\backslash \{x\}}=R'|_{\mathcal {X}\backslash \{x\}}\) holds. Several results prepare the proof of Lemma 16.

Lemma 17

Suppose that \(R'\) is an x-modification of \(R\), and \(V(\mathcal {X}, R') \not = \{x\} \not = V(\mathcal {X}, R)\). Then \(V(\mathcal {X}, R) \backslash \{x\} = V(\mathcal {X}, R') \backslash \{x\}\).

Proof

We have

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array} {r c l l} V(\mathcal {X}, R) \backslash \{x\} &{} = &{} V(\mathcal {X}\backslash \{x\}, R) &{} \quad \text {(SCS and }V(\mathcal {X}, R) \not = \{x\}) \\ &{} = &{} V(\mathcal {X}\backslash \{x\}, R') &{} \quad \text {(IIA)} \\ &{} = &{} V(\mathcal {X}, R') \backslash \{x\} \text {.} &{} \quad \text {(SCS and }V(\mathcal {X}, R') \not = \{x\}) \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Let \(X = \{x_1, \ldots , x_K\}\) denote a set of K alternatives. Take a sequence of preference profiles \(\{R^k\}_{k=0}^{K}\) such that each \(R^k\) is an \(x_{k}\)-modification of \(R^{k-1}\).

Lemma 18

For all \(k \ge 1\), \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^k) \subset V(\mathcal {X}, R^{0}) \cup \{x_{1}, \ldots , x_{k}\}\).

Proof

By induction suppose that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^{k-1}) \subset V(\mathcal {X}, R^{0}) \cup \{x_1, \ldots , x_{k-1}\}\) for some \(k \ge 1\). Then by Lemma 17, \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^{k}) = \{x_{k}\}\) or \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^{k}) \backslash \{x_{k}\} = V(\mathcal {X}, R^{k-1}) \backslash \{x_{k}\}\). \(\square \)

Lemma 19

Suppose that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^0) \not \subset X\). Then for every k, \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^k) \backslash X = V(\mathcal {X}, R^0) \backslash X\).

Proof

This follows from repeated applications of Lemma 17 unless \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^k) = \{x_k\}\) for some k. In this case applying Lemma 18 to the sequence from \(R^k\) to \(R^0\) implies that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^0) \subset \{x_{k}, \ldots , x_{1}\} \subset X\). \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 16

Let \(x \in V(\mathcal {X},R)\). On the contrary suppose that there exists a \(y \in \mathcal {X}\) such that \(y P_i x\) for all \(i \in \mathcal {N}\). Consider \(R'\) such that at \(R'\), \(y P'_i z\) for all \(z \in \mathcal {X}\) and all \(i \in \mathcal {N}\), and \(R'|_{\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{y\}}=R|_{\mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{y\}}\). Then y is strongly Pareto dominant at \(R'\) and so unanimity implies that \(V(\mathcal {X},R')=\{y\}\). Since R is a y-modification of \(R'\), by Lemma 18, \(\{x, y\} \subset V(\mathcal {X},R) \subset V(\mathcal {X},R') = \{y\}\), which is a contradiction. \(\square \)

Lemma 20

The SCC \(\phi \) defined in (14) satisfies unanimity, independence and stability.

Proof

  • Unanimity: If y is weakly Pareto dominant in \(Y \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\) at some \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\), then y is weakly Pareto dominant in \(\mathcal {X}\) at \(R^Y\). By the unanimity of V and (14), \(\phi (Y, R) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^Y) = \{y\}\).

  • Independence: Let \(Y \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\), \(R, R' \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\) and \(R|_Y = R'|_Y\). By the definition of \(\phi \) in (14), \(\phi (Y, R) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^Y)\) and \(\phi (Y, R') = V(\mathcal {X}, {R'}^Y)\). We can construct \({R'}^Y\) from \(R^Y\) through finitely many interim preference profiles \(\{R^k\}\) by repeatedly moving each element \(x^k\) so that for each \(x^k \not \in Y\) and \(y \in Y\) with \(R^Y|_{\{x^k, y\}} \not = {R'}^Y|_{\{x^k, y\}}\), \(R^k|_{\{x^k, y\}} = {R'}^Y|_{\{x^k, y\}}\) holds. By Lemma 16 and Lemma 19, we obtain \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^Y) = V(\mathcal {X}, {R'}^Y)\). Thus, \(\phi (Y, R) = \phi (Y, R')\).

  • Stability: Fix \(X, Y \in \mathscr {P}(\mathcal {X})\) where \(Y \subset X\), and \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\) such that \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \cap Y \ne \varnothing \). Let \(Z = X {\setminus } Y = \{z_1, \ldots , z_K\}\). Define \(Z_0 = \varnothing \) and \(Z_k = \{z_1, \ldots , z_k \}\). Construct \(R^0 = R^X\) and for all \(k>0\), a preference profile \(R^k\) such that \(R^k\) is the \(z_k\)-modification of \(R^{k-1}\) such that \(z_k\) is strongly Pareto dominated by alternatives in \(X {\setminus } \{z_k\}\) at \(R^k\).

Because \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \cap Y \ne \varnothing \), \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \not \subset Z\). By Lemma 19, \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^0) {\setminus } Z = V(\mathcal {X}, R^K) {\setminus } Z\). At the same time, at \(R^K\), alternatives in Z are strongly Pareto dominated by alternatives in Y. Thus, by Lemma 16, \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^K) {\setminus } Z = V(\mathcal {X}, R^K)\). Because \(R^K|_Y = R^Y|_Y\), by the same argument as in the proof of independence, we obtain \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^K) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^Y)\) and hence

$$\begin{aligned} V(\mathcal {X}, R^Y) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) {\setminus } Z \text {.} \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Then by the definition of \(\phi \) in (14), \(V(\mathcal {X}, R^X) \cap Y \ne \varnothing \) implies \(\phi (X, R) \cap Y \ne \varnothing \) and at the same time,

$$\begin{aligned} \phi (Y, R) = \phi (X, R) {\setminus } Z, \end{aligned}$$
(16)

which implies \(\phi (Y, R) = \phi (X, R) \cap Y\). Thus, stability follows. \(\square \)

The “only-if” part proof of Proposition 4

By Lemma 20, the SCC \(\phi \) defined in (14) satisfies unanimity, independence and stability. Then by Theorem 1, \(\phi \) is a serial dictatorship. Thus, a coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters \(\mathscr {U}\) and a tie-breaking rule \(\rho \) induce \(\phi \). Then by Definition 6, for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} \phi (\mathcal {X}, R)=\mathrm {Top}(T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}, R), \rho ). \end{aligned}$$
(17)

By replacing X with \(\mathcal {X}\) in (14), for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} V(\mathcal {X}, R)=\mathrm {Top}(T_{K(R)}(\mathcal {X}, R), \rho ). \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, a coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters \(\mathscr {U}\) and a tie-breaking rule \(\rho \) also induce V for \(\mathcal {X}\). To show the result for any agenda domain, fix \(x \in \mathcal {X}\). Let \(A = \mathcal {X}{\setminus } \{x\}\). Then similarly to (17), for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} \phi (A, R)=\mathrm {Top}(T_{K(R)}(A, R), \rho ). \end{aligned}$$

By replacing X with A in (14), for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\),

$$\begin{aligned} V(A, R^{A})=\mathrm {Top}(T_{K(R)}(A, R), \rho ). \end{aligned}$$

By SCS, for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\), \(V(A, R) = V(\mathcal {X}, R) {\setminus } \{x\}\) and \(V(A, R^A) = V(\mathcal {X}, R^A) {\setminus } \{x\}\). By IIA, \(V(A, R) = V(A, R^A)\) for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\). Finally, for all \(R \in \mathcal {R}^{\mathcal {N}}\), \(V(A, R^A) = V(A, R)\), and thus

$$\begin{aligned} V(A, R)=\mathrm {Top}(T_{K(R)}(A, R), \rho ). \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, a coherent hierarchy of ultrafilters \(\mathscr {U}\) and a tie-breaking rule \(\rho \) also induce V. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Takayama, S., Yokotani, A. Social choice correspondences with infinitely many agents: serial dictatorship. Soc Choice Welf 48, 573–598 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1025-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1025-0

Navigation