Skip to main content
Log in

On restricted bargaining sets

  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we analyze the behavior of bargaining sets in continuum economies when there are restrictions on the formation of coalitions. We provide several characterizations of Vind’s (J Math Econ 21:89–97, 1992) bargaining set in terms of its restricted versions, where not all the coalitions are formed. Moreover, we show that these equivalences do not hold for Mas-Colell’s (J Math Econ 18:129–139, 1989) bargaining set. These findings highlight the different nature of both notions of bargaining sets. Finally, we illustrate the impossibility of extrapolating our results to a more general setting.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A feasible allocation is said to be robustly efficient in an economy if it is not blocked by the grand coalition in a collection of economies obtained by perturbing the initial endowments. See Hervés-Beloso and Moreno-García (2008) for further details.

  2. An allocation \(f\) is strongly blocked by the coalition \(S\) if there is an attainable allocation \(g\) for \(S\) such that \(g(t) \succ _{t} f(t)\) for every \(t \in S.\)

  3. Schmeidler proved that if an allocation \(f\) is blocked by a coalition \(S\) via an allocation \(g,\) then, for any \(\varepsilon >0\), \(f\) is also blocked via the same allocation \(g\) by a coalition \(S'\subset S,\) with \(\mu (S') \le \varepsilon .\)

  4. This is because the mapping that associates each agent to her preference relation and initial endowments is measurable. Thus, given \(\varepsilon >0\), Lusin’s theorem guarantees the existence of a compact set of measure greater than \(1- \varepsilon \) where this mapping is continous.

  5. An allocation \(h\) (feasible or not) is dominated (or blocked by the grand coalition) in an economy if there exists a feasible allocation \(g\) in such an economy such that every consumer \(t\) prefers \(g(t)\) rather than \(h(t).\)

  6. An objection \((S,g)\) to \(f\) is said to be Walrasian if there exists a price system \(p\) such that (i) \(p \cdot v \ge p \cdot \omega (t)\) if \(v \succsim _t g(t)\), \(t\in S\) and (ii) \(p \cdot v \ge p \cdot \omega (t)\) if \(v \succsim _{t} f(t)\), \(t\notin S.\)

  7. Some calculations show that \(\hat{\alpha }= \frac{\sqrt{115}-5}{3}.\)

  8. We remark that Schmeidler’s (1972), Grodal’s (1972) and Vind’s (1972) characterizations of the core for atomless economies rely crucially on Lyapunov’s convexity theorem which does not hold in an infinite dimensional set up. In spite of this, under further assumptions, there are extensions of these core characterizations to economies with an infinite dimensional commodity space (see, for instance, Hervés-Beloso et al. 2000; Evren and Hüsseinov 2008; Pesce 2010). Accordingly, the example we state is in connection with this analysis.

  9. For example, we can take a non-negligible Cantor subset \(A_{0}^{1}\) of \(I_{0}^{1}=I;\) then we take again non-negligible Cantor subsets \(A_{1}^{1} \) and \(A_{1}^{2}\) of \(I_{1}^{1} \setminus A_{0}^{1}\) and \(I_{1}^{2} \setminus A_{0}^{1}\) respectively, with the property that \(\mu (A_{0}^{1} \bigcap I_{1}^{1})+ \mu (A_{1}^{1}) = \mu (A_{0}^{1} \bigcap I_{1}^{2})+ \mu (A_{1}^{2});\) and so on. In this way, \(A= \bigcup _{n=0}^{\infty } \bigcup _{i=1}^{2^{n}} A_{n}^{i}\) and, for any \(n\) we have that \(\mu (A\bigcap I_{n}^{i})= \frac{\mu (A)}{2^{n}},\) for all \(i= 1, \ldots , 2^{n}.\)

  10. Recall that the Mackey topology coincides with the weak star topology on bounded subsets of \(\ell ^{\infty }.\)

  11. This point is in accordance with the work by Hervés-Beloso et al. (2000), who have extended Schmeidler’s and Grodal’s results to an infinite dimensional setting by requiring a kind of myopic behavior of the agents.

References

  • Aumann RJ (1964) Markets with a continuum of traders. Econometrica 32:39–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann R, Maschler M (1964) The bargaining set for cooperative games. In: Dresher M, Shapley LS, Tucker AW (eds) Advances in game theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, pp 443–447

    Google Scholar 

  • Evren O, Hüsseinov F (2008) Theorems on the core of an economy with infinitely many commodities and consumers. J Math Econ 44:1180–1196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grodal B (1972) A second remark on the core of an atomless economy. Econometrica 40:581–583

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hervés-Beloso C, Moreno-García E, Núñez-Sanz C, Páscoa M (2000) Blocking efficacy of small coalitions in myopic economies. J Econ Theory 93:72–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hervés-Beloso C, Moreno-García E (2008) Competitive equilibria and the grand coalition. J Math Econ 44:697–706

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell A (1989) An equivalence theorem for a bargaining set. J Math Econ 18:129–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostroy JM, Zame WR (1994) Nonatomic economies and the boundaries of perfect competition. Econometrica 62:593–633

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pesce M (2010) On mixed markets with asymmetric information. Econ Theory 45:23–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schjødt U, Sloth B (1994) Bargaining sets with small coalitions. Int J Game Theory 23:49–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler D (1972) A remark on the core of an atomless economy. Econometrica 40:579–580

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vind K (1972) A third remark on the core of an atomless economy. Econometrica 40:585–586

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vind K (1992) Two characterizations of bargaining sets. J Math Econ 21:89–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work is partially supported by the Research Grants ECO2012-38860-C02-01 and 02 (Ministerio de Economía y Competitividad), RGEA and 10PXIB300141PR (Xunta de Galicia and FEDER). We are grateful to N. Allouch, J. Correia-da-Silva, M. Faias, G. Graziano, C. Hervés-Beloso, L. Koutsougeras, J. P. Torres-Martínez, the participants in the Simposio de la Asociación Española de Economía, December, 2012, and in the Naples Workshop on Economic Theory, January, 2013. We also thank an associated editor and two anonymous referees for comments and suggestions that indeed helped to improve the final version of this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emma Moreno-García.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Lemma 3.1

Since \((T,h)\) is a counter-objection to \((S,g)\) we have that \(h\) is a feasible allocation, it is also attainable for \(T\) and every \(t \in T\) prefers \(h(t)\) rather than \(g(t).\) By Lyapunov’s convexity theorem, for every \(\varepsilon >0,\) there exists a coalition \(H_{\varepsilon } \subset T,\) such that \(h\) is attainable for \(H_{\varepsilon }\) and then \((H_{\varepsilon }, h)\) is also a counter-objection to \((S,g)\) (see the proof in Schmeidler (1972) for further details).

As in Grodal (1972) let \((t_{n}, n \in \mathbb {N})\) be a dense subset in \(H_{\varepsilon }.\) Define \(H^{1}_{\varepsilon } = H_{\varepsilon } \cap B(t_{1}, \varepsilon /2)\) and \(H^{n}_{\varepsilon } = H_{\varepsilon } \cap B(t_{n}, \varepsilon /2) \setminus \cup _{k=1}^{n-1} H_{\varepsilon }^{k},\) for \(n >1.\) Let \( h_{n}= \int _{H^{n}_{\varepsilon }} \left( h(t) - \omega (t)\right) d \! \mu (t).\) Define \(\mathcal{C}\) as the convex hull of the set \(\Gamma =\{ h_{n} | n \in N\},\) where \(N= \{n \in \mathbb {N}| \mu ( H^{n}_{\varepsilon }) >0 \}.\) Now let \(\chi \) be the smallest affine subspace containing \(\mathcal{C}.\) Note that \(\sum _{n \in N} h_{n} =0\) and 0 belongs to the interior of \(\mathcal{C}\) relative to \(\chi \subset \mathbb {R}^{\ell }.\) By Caratheodory’s theorem, there is \(A \subset N\) with at most \(\ell +1\) elements such that we can write \(0= \sum _{j \in A} \alpha _{j} h_{j},\) with \(\alpha _{j} \in [0,1]\) and \(\sum _{j \in A} \alpha _{j}=1.\) Lyapunov’s theorem allows us to guarantee that for each \(j \in A\) there exists \(H_{j} \subset H^{j}_{\varepsilon }\) such that \(\mu (H_{j}) = \alpha _{j} \mu (H^{j}_{\varepsilon })\) and \( \int _{H_{j}} \left( h(t) - \omega (t)\right) d \! \mu (t) = \alpha _{j} h_{j}.\) Therefore, by construction, the coalition \(H=\cup _{j \in A} H_{j}\) belongs to \(\mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon }\) and counter-objects \((S,g)\) via \(h\). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3.1

Let us first prove that \(B^{*}(\mathcal{E}) \subset B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E})\). Indeed, assume that \(f\) is a feasible allocation such that \(f \in B^{*}(\mathcal{E}) \setminus B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E})\). Since \(f \notin B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E})\), there exists a global objection \((S,g)\) to \(f\), with \(S \in \mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon }\), for which there is no counter-objection \((C,y)\) such that \(C \in \mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon },\) and by Lemma 3.1, this is the same as saying that it does not exist any counter-objection to \((S,g)\). This means that \(f\) is global objected but not counter-objected, so \(f \notin B^{*}(\mathcal{E})\).

We will now prove that \(B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E}) \subset B^{*}(\mathcal{E})\). Let \(f \in B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E})\), and let \((S,g)\) be a global objection to \(f\). By Lyapunov’s and Caratheodory’s theorems (see the proof of the Lemma 3.1) we can guarantee the existence of \(K\subset S\) such that \(K \in \mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon }\) and \( \int _{K} g(t) d \!\mu (t) \le \int _{K} \omega (t) d \!\mu (t)\), meaning that \((K,g)\) is also a global objection to \(f\). Since \(f \in B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E})\), \((K,g)\) necessarily has a counter-objection \((C,y)\), with \(C \in \mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon },\) which is straightforward also a counter-objection to \((S,g)\), concluding that \(f \in B^{*}(\mathcal{E})\). \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 3.2

Since \((T,h)\) is a counter-objection to \((S,g)\), the following holds:

  1. (i)

    \(\int _T h(t) d\! \mu (t) \le \int _T \omega (t) d\! \mu (t)\) and

  2. (ii)

    \(h(t) \succ _{t} g(t)\) for almost all \(t \in T.\)

If \(\alpha < \mu (T),\) consider the measure \(\nu (A)= \left( \mu (A), \int _{A} (h(t) -\omega (t)) d\! \mu (t) \right) \) restricted to measurable subsets of the coalition \(T.\) By Lyapunov’s convexity theorem we obtain that there exists \(T_{\alpha } \subset T,\) with \(\mu (T_{\alpha })= \alpha ,\) that blocks the allocation \(g\) via the same \(h\).

Consider \(\alpha > \mu (T).\) Let the measure \(\eta (A)= \left( \mu (A), \int _{A} (h(t) -g(t)) d\! \mu (t) \right) \) restricted to subsets of \(T. \) Applying Lyapunov’s convexity theorem we obtain that for any \(\beta \in (0,1)\) there exits \(A \subset T\) such that \(\mu (A)= \beta \mu (T)\) and \( \int _{A} (h(t) -g(t)) d\! \mu (t) = \beta \int _{T} (h(t) -g(t)) d\! \mu (t).\) By continuity and measurability, there exist \(\tilde{h}\) and \(\delta > 0\) such that \( \int _{A} \tilde{h} (t) d\! \mu (t) = \int _{A} h(t) d\! \mu (t) - \delta \) and \(\tilde{h}(t) \succ g(t)\) for every \(t \in A.\)

Let the allocation \(z\) defined as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} z(t)= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \tilde{h}(t) &{} \hbox {if }\quad t \in A, \\ g(t) + \frac{\delta }{\mu (T\setminus A)} &{} \hbox {if }\quad t \in T\setminus A. \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

Note that \(\int _{T} z(t) d\!\mu (t) = \int _{T} \left( \beta h(t) + (1 - \beta ) g(t) \right) d \!\mu (t)\) and \(z(t) \succ g(t)\) for every \(t \in T.\) As before, there exists \(\gamma >0\) and \(\tilde{z}\) such that \(\int _{T} \tilde{z}(t) d\!\mu (t) = \int _{T} z(t) d\!\mu (t) - \gamma \) and \(\tilde{z}(t) \succ g(t)\) for every \(t \in T.\) Applying Lyapunov’s theorem again to the above measure \(\nu \) restricted to \(I \setminus T,\) we have that there exists \(B \subset I \setminus T\) such that \(\mu (B)= (1 - \beta ) \mu (I\setminus T)\) and \(\int _{B} \left( g(t) - \omega (t) \right) d\! \mu (t) = (1- \beta ) \int _{ I \setminus T} \left( g(t) - \omega (t) \right) d\! \mu (t)\).

The coalition \(C= T \cup B\) blocks \(g\) via de allocation \(y\) given by

$$\begin{aligned} y(t)= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \tilde{z}(t) &{} \hbox {if}\;\quad t \in T, \\ g(t) + \frac{\gamma }{\mu (B)} &{} \hbox {if} \;\quad t \in B \; \mathrm{and }\\ \omega (t) &{} \hbox { otherwise.} \; \;\end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

By construction \(y\) is a feasible allocation and \(\int _{C} y(t) d \! \mu (t) \le \int _{C} \omega (t) d \! \mu (t).\) Taking \(\beta = ( 1 - \alpha ) / (1 - \mu (T)),\) we conclude that \(\mu (C)= \alpha \). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3.2

We follow the same proof as in Theorem 3.1. To prove that \(B^{*}(\mathcal{E}) \subset \alpha -B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E}),\) we apply Lemma 3.2 instead of Lemma 3.1, and to show that \( \alpha -B^{*}_{\varepsilon }(\mathcal{E}) \subset B^{*}(\mathcal{E})\) it is important to remark that if \((S,g)\) is a global objection to \(f,\) then there exists \(K \in \mathcal{S}_{\varepsilon }\) such that \((K, g)\) is also a global objection to \(f.\) That is, both coalitions \(S\) and \(K\) use the same feasible allocation \(g\) which is crucial in the proof. \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 3.3

Let \((S,g)\) be a full objection to \(f.\) Since \(g\) has no counter-objection, \(g\) is in the core. Let \(p\) a price system such that \((p,g)\) is a competitive equilibrium for the economy \(\mathcal{E}.\) Suppose that there exist a coalition \(T\) and a number \(\alpha \in (0,1]\) such that \(g\) is dominated in the economy \(\mathcal{E}(T, g, \alpha ),\) that is, there exists an allocation \(h\) which is feasible in the perturbed economy \(\mathcal{E}(T, g, \alpha )\) and \(h(t) \succ _{t} g(t)\) for almost all \(t \in I.\) Then, we have that \( p \cdot h(t) > p \cdot \omega (t) \ge p \cdot g(t),\) for almost all agent \(t \in I.\)

Multiplying the above inequalities by \((1-\alpha )\) and by \(\alpha ,\) respectively, we obtain \( p \cdot h(t) > p \cdot ((1- \alpha ) \ \omega (t) + \alpha \ g(t)) \) for almost all agent \(t \in T.\) Therefore, we have \( \int _{I} p \cdot h(t) \ d\!\mu (t) > \int _{I\setminus T} p \cdot \omega (t) d\!\mu (t) \ + \ \int _{T} p \cdot \left( (1-\alpha ) \omega (t) + \alpha g(t) \right) \ d\!\mu (t) = \int _{I} p \cdot \omega (T,g,\alpha )(t) \ d\!\mu (t), \) which is a contradiction with the feasibility of \(h\) in the economy \(\mathcal{E}(T,g, \alpha ).\)

To show the converse, let \(g\) a non-dominated allocation for every economy \(\mathcal{E}(A,g,\alpha ).\) Assume that \((S,g)\) has a counter-objection, namely \((T,z).\) Arguing as in the proof of Lemma 3.2, we can take \(z\) such that \( \int _{T} z(t) d\! \mu (t) \le \int _{T} \omega (t) d\! \mu (t) - \delta ,\) with \(\delta > 0\) and moreover, given any \(\alpha \in (0,1),\) there exists an allocation \(y: T \rightarrow \mathbb {R}^{\ell }_{+}\) such that \( \int _{T} y(t) d\! \mu (t) = \int _{T} (\alpha z(t) + (1-\alpha ) g(t)) d\! \mu (t)\) and \(y(t) \succ _{t} f(t)\) for every \(t \in T.\) Let us consider the allocation \(h: I \rightarrow \mathbb {R}^{\ell }_{+}\) given by

$$\begin{aligned} h(t)= \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} y(t) &{} \hbox {if }\quad t \in T \; \mathrm{and }\\ g(t) + \frac{\alpha }{\mu (I\setminus T)} \ \delta &{} \hbox {if }\quad t \in I \setminus T. \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

By construction, we can deduce \( \int _{I} (h(t) - \omega (I \setminus T,g, \alpha )(t)) d\! \mu (t) = (1 -\alpha ) \int _{I} ( g(t) - \omega (t)) d\! \mu (t) \le 0.\) Therefore, the grand coalition blocks \(g\) via \(h\) in the economy \(\mathcal{E}(I\setminus T, g, \alpha ),\) which is a contradiction with the fact that \(g\) is a non dominated allocation for every economy \(\mathcal{E}(A, g, \alpha )\). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3.3

It is enough to apply Lemma 3.3 and follow the same proof as in Theorem 3.1 and 3.2. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hervés-Estévez, J., Moreno-García, E. On restricted bargaining sets. Int J Game Theory 44, 631–645 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-014-0447-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-014-0447-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation