Skip to main content

Biological Explanation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

One of the central aims of science is explanation: scientists seek to uncover why things happen the way they do. This chapter addresses what kinds of explanations are formulated in biology, how explanatory aims influence other features of the field of biology, and the implications of all of this for biology education. Philosophical treatments of scientific explanation have been both complicated and enriched by attention to explanatory strategies in biology. Most basically, whereas traditional philosophy of science based explanation on derivation from scientific laws, there are many biological explanations in which laws play little or no role. Instead, the field of biology is a natural place to turn for support for the idea that causal information is explanatory. Biology has also been used to motivate mechanistic accounts of explanation, as well as criticisms of that approach. Ultimately, the most pressing issue about explanation in biology may be how to account for the wide range of explanatory styles encountered in the field. This issue is crucial, for the aims of biological explanation influence a variety of other features of the field of biology. Explanatory aims account for the continued neglect of some central causal factors, a neglect that would otherwise be mysterious. This is linked to the persistent use of models like evolutionary game theory and population genetic models, models that are simplified to the point of unreality. These explanatory aims also offer a way to interpret many biologists’ total commitment to one or another methodological approach, and the intense disagreements that result. In my view, such debates are better understood as arising not from different theoretical commitments, but commitments to different explanatory projects. Biology education would thus be enriched by attending to approaches to biological explanation, as well as the unexpected ways that these explanatory aims influence other features of biology. I suggest five lessons for teaching about explanation in biology that follow from the considerations of this chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For the sake of simplicity, I use the word “phenomenon” throughout this chapter to stand in for various conceptions of the target of explanation: events or laws, propositions, explananda, etc. Such distinctions are not central to the aim of this chapter.

  2. 2.

    A trait’s fitness is a measure of the trait’s relative contribution to organisms’ ability to survive and reproduce. However, the concept of fitness is vexed; see Rosenberg and Bouchard (2010) for an overview of the difficulties.

  3. 3.

    Mayr’s distinction between proximate and ultimate causes can be construed as a distinction between explanations of why members of a population have some trait (evolutionary/ultimate causes) and explanations of how members of the population came to have that trait (proximate/developmental causes). This proximate/ultimate distinction has received a good amount of attention in philosophy of biology. Ariew (2003) reinterprets the distinction as distinguishing between dynamical versus statistical explanations. Laland et al. (2011) argue that Mayr’s distinction fails because the types of causes distinguished are interrelated.

  4. 4.

    This approach analyzes games for points of stability, e.g., evolutionary stable strategies (Maynard Smith and Price 1973). A different approach to evolutionary game theory instead specifies population dynamics, e.g., replicator dynamics, and thus results in dynamical models.

References

  • Amos, C.I., M.R. Spitz, and P. Cinciripini. 2010. Chipping away at the genetics of smoking behavior. Nature Genetics 42(5): 366–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. 2003. Ernst Mayr’s ‘Ultimate/Proximate’ distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biology and Philosophy 18: 553–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barros, D.B. 2008. Natural selection as a mechanism. Philosophy of Science 75: 306–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2006. Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and A. Abrahamsen. 2005. Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1990. Organism and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1997. Does biology have laws? The experimental evidence. Philosophy of Science 64(4): 444–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. 2013. Explanation in biology: Reduction, pluralism, and explanatory aims. Science Education 22(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J.S. 2001. Fit of form and function, diversity of life, and procession of life as an evolutionary game. In Adaptationism and optimality, ed. S.H. Orzack and E. Sober, 114–160. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C.F. 2007. Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. 1957. Laws and explanation in history. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eshel, I., M. Feldman, and A. Bergman. 1998. Long-term evolution, short-term evolution, and population genetic theory. Journal of Theoretical Biology 191: 391–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. 2010. Confirmation and explaining how possible. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41(1): 32–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1974. Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy 71(1): 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44(1): 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2006. The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy 21: 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goss-Custard, J.D. 1977. Predator responses and prey mortality in redshank, Tringatotanus (L.), and a preferred prey, Corophiumvolutator (Pallas). Journal of Animal Ecology 46: 21–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen, A. 1984. Natural selection, kin selection, and group selection. In Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach, 2nd ed, ed. J.R. Krebs and N.B. Davies. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammerstein, P. 1996. Streetcar theory and long-term evolution. Science 273(5278): 1032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C., and P. Oppenheim. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15: 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. 1992. The particular circumstance model of scientific explanation. In History and evolution, ed. M. Nitecki and D. Nitecki, 69–80. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K., and V. Zogza. 2009. Preliminary evolutionary explanations: A basic framework for conceptual change and explanatory coherence in evolution. Science Education 18: 1313–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1981. Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science 48(4): 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1984. 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. Philosophical Review 93: 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1989. Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, Scientific explanation, vol. 13, ed. P. Kitcher and W.C. Salmon, 410–505. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. 2007. Explaining with equilibria. In Rethinking explanation, ed. J. Persson and P. Ylikoski, 149–162. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K., K. Sterelny, J. Odling-Smee, W. Hoppitt, and T. Uller. 2011. Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334: 1512–1516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. 1966. The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist 54(4): 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C.F. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67(1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., and G. Price. 1973. The logic of animal conflict. Nature 246: 15–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134: 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. 2007. Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics 8: 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. 2010a. Explanatory independence and epistemic interdependence: A case study of the optimality approach. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61(1): 213–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. 2010b. Levels of explanation reconceived. Philosophy of Science 77(1): 59–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. 2011. Explanation and understanding: An alternative to Strevens’ depth. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1(1): 29–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. 2013. Defusing Ideological Defenses in Biology. BioScience 63(2): 118–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A., and F. Bouchard. Fitness. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2010), ed. E. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/fitness/.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. 2009. The genial gene: Deconstructing Darwinian selfishness. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1970. Are there laws in biology? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48(2): 234–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C. 1989. Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C. 1998. Causality and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. 1962. Explanations, predictions, and laws. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, Scientific explanation, space, and time, vol. 3, ed. H. Feigl and G. Maxwell, 170–230. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R.A., and R.L. Millstein. 2005. Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science 36(2): 327–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1999. The multiple realizability argument against reduction. Philosophy of Science 66: 542–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 1996. Explanatory pluralism in evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy 11: 193–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2004. The causal and unification accounts of explanation unified—Causally. Nous 38: 154–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. 2009. Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. 1990. Why the antireductionist consensus won’t survive the case of classical Mendelian genetics. Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings 1: 125–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. 2006. Forty years of ‘The Strategy’: Levins on model building and idealization. Biology and Philosophy 21: 623–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, G.S. 1984. Reciprocal food sharing in the vampire bat. Nature 308: 181–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W.C. 1987. False models as means to truer theories. In Neutral models in biology, ed. N. Nitecki and A. Hoffman, 23–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 2003. Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments 

Thanks to Francis Cartieri for assistance on this project. I also appreciate getting helpful feedback on earlier drafts from Francis Cartieri, Kostas Kampourakis, and an anonymous referee for this volume.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Angela Potochnik .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Potochnik, A. (2013). Biological Explanation. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics