Skip to main content
Log in

Forty Years of ‘The Strategy’: Levins on Model Building and Idealization

  • Published:
Biology and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper is an interpretation and defense of Richard Levins’ “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology,” which has been extremely influential among biologists since its publication 40 years ago. In this article, Levins confronted some of the deepest philosophical issues surrounding modeling and theory construction. By way of interpretation, I discuss each of Levins’ major philosophical themes: the problem of complexity, the brute-force approach, the existence and consequence of tradeoffs, and robustness analysis. I argue that Levins’ article is concerned, at its core, with justifying the use of multiple, idealized models in population biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I put this point carefully because some models are studied for their intrinsic interest, with no expectation that a real-world phenomenon corresponds to them. Analyses of perpetual motion machine models, three-sex biology models, and models of non-aromatic cyclohexatriene are examples of such a situation.

  2. For further discussion about this issue and the strategies of abstraction employed to deal with it, see Richard Levins’ contribution to this volume.

  3. I thank Glen Ierley for pointing out why many theorists see this as the main advantage of analytical solutions.

  4. In conversation, Grigori Mints suggested that such a full analysis gives you essentially everything you would want from an analytical solution. Thus it is not entirely clear that such a full characterization isn’t some form of an analytical solution, although not an algebraic solution expressed in closed form.

  5. The epistemolgical issues raised by computational science is one of the major themes of Humphreys (2004).

  6. Levins (1993) contains a more detailed discussion of realism, and is the source for the broader interpretation of its scope.

  7. One possible way for Levins to avoid the conflaction of the brute-force approach and the first strategy is to point out that there are different loci for generality. One may be committed to a research program that is highly general, but which will require brute-force models for individual phenomena. So the techniques can remain general, while the individual models are not. Perhaps this allows for a brute force strategy that is not, strictly speaking, the first strategy of model building.

  8. Subsequent research (e.g., Seger and Brockmann 1987) has called in to question whether this particular phenomenon is actually robust.

References

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford, The Clarendon Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1974) Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy 71:5–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (this volume) The strategy of model based science. Biol Philos

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2005) Folk psychology as a model. Philoso Imprint 5(6)

  • Humphreys P (2004) Extending ourselves. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1981) Explanatory Unification. Philosophy of Science 48:507–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1962) Theory of fitness in a heterogeneous environment I. The fitness set and adaptive function. Amer Nat 96(861):361–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. In: Sober E (ed) Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology, 1st ed. Cambridge MA, MIT Press, pp 18–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments. Princeton, Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R (1993) A response to Orzack and Sober: formal analysis and the fluidity of science. Quart Rev Biol 68(4):547–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins R, Lewontin R (1985) The dialectical biologist. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins R, MacArthur RH (1966) The maintenance of genetic polymorphism in a spatially heterogenous environment. Amer Nat 100:585–589

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediating instruments. In: Morgan M, Morrison M (eds) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 10–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak MA, May RM (2000) Virus dynamics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh J (2003) Complex systems, trade-offs and mathematical modeling: a response to Sober and Orzack. Philos Sci 70:1496–1507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odum HT (1983) Systems ecology: an introduction. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Orzack SH, Sober E (1993) A critical assessment of Levins’s the strategy of model building in population biology (1966). Quart Rev Biol 68(4):533–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden J (1979) Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: an introduction. Macmillan Publishing Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Seger J, Brockmann HJ (1987) What is bet-hedging? Oxford Surveys Evol Biol 4:181–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (ed.) (1984) Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology, 1st ed. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal RR, Rohlf FJ (1981) Biometry, 2nd ed. Freeman WH, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens M (2004) The causal and unification approachs to explanation unified—causally. Noûs 38:154–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe F (1977) The search for philosophic understanding of scientific theories. In: Suppe F (ed) The structure of scientific theories, 2nd ed. Chicago, University of Illinois Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1960a) A comparison of the meaning and use of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences. Synthese 12:287–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1960b) Models of data. Stanford, Stanford University Press, pp 251–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Volterra V (1926) Fluctuations in the abundance of a species considered mathematically. Nature 118:558–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Watt KEF (1956) The choice and solution of mathematical models for predicting and maximizing the yield of a fishery. J Fish Res Board of Canada 13:613–345

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2003) When less is more: tradeoffs and idealization in model building. Ph.D. thesis, Stanford University

  • Weisberg M (2004) Qualitative theory and chemical explanation. Philos Sci 71:1071–1081

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg M (2006) Robustness analysis. Philos Sci 73(5), in press

  • Weisberg M (manuscript-a), Three kinds of idealization

  • Weisberg M (2007) Who is a modeler? Brit J Philos Sci 58(2), in press

  • Weisberg M, Reisman K (manuscript-b) The robust volterra principle

  • Weisstein EW (2003) CRC concise encylopedia of mathematics, 2nd ed. Boca Raton, Chapman & Hall

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiegert RG (1975) Simulation models of ecosystems. Annl Rev Evol Syst 6:311–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1981) Robustness, reliability, overdetermination. In: Brewer M, Collins B (eds) Scientific inquiry and the social sciences. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass, pp 124–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1987) False models as a means to Truer theories. In: Nitecki M, Hoffmann A (eds) Neutral models in biology. Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp 23–55

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article developed out of several years’ reflection about Richard Levins’ methodological work, which Peter Godfrey-Smith first introduced me to at Stanford. I thank Peter, Brett Calcot, Marc Feldman, Patrick Forber, Richard Lewontin, Elisabeth Lloyd, John Mathewson, Jay Odenbaugh, Ken Reisman, Joan Roughgarden, Deena Skolnick Weisberg, Kim Sterelny, Angela Potochnik, Michael Strevens, Ward Watt, and Bill Wimsatt for many extremely stimulating discussions about Levins’ ideas. Thanks also to the attendees of the Greater Philadelphia Philosophy Consortium conference on “The Strategy” and Levins’ work, but special thanks go to my colleagues Zoltan Domotor, Gary Hatfield, and Scott Weinstein. All those who have worked with Dick Levins will know how stimulating and intellectually generous he is. He has answered innumerable questions and given very stimulating feedback. Along with other philosophers of biology writing about modeling and idealization, I owe him the utmost thanks for his kindness and support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Weisberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Weisberg, M. Forty Years of ‘The Strategy’: Levins on Model Building and Idealization. Biol Philos 21, 623–645 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9051-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-006-9051-9

Keywords

Navigation