Skip to main content

Contextualism in Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science

Abstract

I introduce a contextualist theory of epistemic justification in order to defend Helen Longino’s contextual empiricism against three criticisms. The critics claim that contextual empiricism (1) implies dogmatism with respect to standards of argumentation, (2) lacks naturalistic justification, and (3) implies relativism with respect to moral and social values. I argue that the three criticisms fail. If we understand contextual empiricism as a contextualist theory of epistemic justification, standards of argumentation do not need to be adopted dogmatically, Longino’s social account of objectivity is justified in virtue of advancing epistemic responsibility, and her account of objectivity does not imply that any moral and social values are acceptable in scientific debates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

     In The Fate of Knowledge (2002), Longino suggests that critical contextual empiricism is an even more appropriate term for her theory than mere contextual empiricism because it emphasizes the social aspect in contextual empiricism (208).

  2. 2.

     Longino discusses David Annis’s (1978) and Stewart Cohen’s (1987) contextualist theories of epistemic justification but not Williams’s (2001) contextualism (see Longino 2002, 104–106).

  3. 3.

     By contextual values Longino means value judgments concerning what is morally acceptable or praiseworthy, or what is a desirable social order (1990, 4). By constitutive values she means values that are generated from an understanding of the goals of science (1990, 4). So whereas such values as truth, consistency, and explanatory power are constitutive values in science, moral and social values such as equality and justice are contextual values in science. In her essay ‘Gender, Politics, and the Theoretical Virtues’ (1995), Longino suggests that the distinction between constitutive and contextual values is not as clear-cut as she had assumed in Science as Social Knowledge (1990).

  4. 4.

     See Anderson (1995) and Rolin (2002) for a response to Haack’s (2003) critique and Rolin (2006) for a response to Pinnick’s (2003) critique of feminist epistemology in Scrutinizing Feminist Epistemology.

  5. 5.

     Like Longino, many philosophers argue that philosophy of science should account for the persistence of the diversity of standards throughout the history of science (see e.g., Kuhn 1970; Rolin 2010; Solomon 2001).

  6. 6.

     Philip Kitcher (1994) argues that Longino’s contextual empiricism collapses into relativism with respect to truth because Longino identifies truth with consensus belief in communities that follow certain types of procedures (1994, 132, note 26). As K. Brad Wray points out, Kitcher’s criticism is based on the mistaken premise that Longino identifies truth with consensus belief in a community (Wray 1999, 545). This premise is false because Longino does not accept the view that knowledge entails truth (1990, 93). In Longino’s view, acceptance of a theory or a hypothesis involves a belief in its empirical adequacy (1990, 94).

  7. 7.

     In a more recent paper Solomon (2006) cites evidence in support of the claim that the practice of rational deliberation recommended by Longino does not always lead to epistemic success. Irving Janis’s work suggests that a group that deliberates with the aim of reaching a consensus is vulnerable to the so called ‘groupthink’ phenomenon (Solomon 2006, 31). Such a phenomenon takes place when peer pressure and pressure from those in authority leads dissenting individuals to change their minds or not to share their knowledge of contrary evidence. As a result, the outcome of group deliberation is biased in the sense that it does not reflect all the information that individual group members have. I would argue that even if there is such a phenomenon as ‘groupthink’ it is less likely to take place in scientific communities than in research teams because scientific communities are socially more dispersed than research teams. Insofar as equality of intellectual authority is respected scientific communities, as Longino recommends it be, scientific communities are unlikely to be subject to ‘groupthink.’ Ideally, such communities are open to outside criticism. As Alison Wylie (2006) argues, evidence of the ‘groupthink’ phenomenon does not support the hypothesis that the aggregation of opinion is epistemically superior to rational deliberation. It shows merely that under certain circumstances rational deliberation may fail (2006, 44).

  8. 8.

     Williams stresses that both conceptions of epistemic justification, justification as epistemic responsibility and as having adequate grounds, are necessary elements in an adequate theory of knowledge (2001, 23).

  9. 9.

     For example, the standard of consistency can be given a justification on the grounds that it is derived from the epistemic value of truth.

References

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 1995. Knowledge, human interests, and objectivity. Philosophical Topics 23(2): 27–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2004. Uses of value judgments in science: A general argument, with lessons from a case study of feminist research on divorce. Hypatia 19(1): 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. 2005. How not to criticize feminist epistemology: Review of Pinnick, Koertge, and Almeder. http://www-personal.umich.edu/~eandersn/hownotreview.html. Accessed 5 May 2005.

  • Annis, David. 1978. A contextualist theory of epistemic justification. American Philosophical Quarterly 15(3): 213–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clough, Sharyn. 1998. A hasty retreat from evidence: The recalcitrance of relativism in feminist epistemology. Hypatia 13(4): 88–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clough, Sharyn. 2003. Beyond epistemology: A pragmatist approach to feminist science studies. Lanham/Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Stewart. 1987. Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthese 73(1): 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crasnow, Sharon. 2003. Can science be objective? Feminism, relativism, and objectivity. In Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: An examination of gender in science, ed. Cassandra L. Pinnick, Noretta Koertge, and Robert F. Almeder, 130–141. New Brunswick/London: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, Keith. 2009. The case for contextualism. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, Anne. 2000. Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan. 1996. Science as social? – Yes and No. In Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science, ed. Lynn H. Nelson and Jack Nelson, 79–93. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan. 2003. Knowledge and propaganda: Reflections of an old feminist. In Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: An examination of gender in science, ed. Cassandra L. Pinnick, Noretta Koertge, and Robert F. Almeder, 7–19. New Brunswick/London: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and intervening: Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intemann, Kristen. 2008. Increasing the number of feminist scientists: Why feminist aims are not served by the underdetermination thesis. Science & Education 17(10): 1065–1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 1994. Contrasting conceptions of social epistemology. In Socializing epistemology, ed. Frederick F. Schmitt, 111–134. Lanham/London: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, Janet. 2005. A feminist primer for philosophers of science. In Philosophy – Science – Scientific philosophy, ed. Christian Nimtz and Ansgar Beckermann, 287–305. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Elizabeth. 2005. The case of the female orgasm: Bias in the science of evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen. 1990. Science as social knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen. 1995. Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese 104(3): 383–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, Helen. 2002. The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick, Cassandra. 2003. Feminist epistemology: Implications for the philosophy of science. In Scrutinizing feminist epistemology: An examination of gender in science, ed. Cassandra L. Pinnick, Noretta Koertge, and Robert F. Almeder, 20–30. New Brunswick/London: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinnick, Cassandra. 2005. The failed feminist challenge to “fundamental epistemology”. Science & Education 14: 103–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, Kristina. 2002. Is “science as social” a feminist insight? Social Epistemology 16(3): 233–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, Kristina. 2004. Why gender is a relevant factor in the social epistemology of scientific inquiry. Philosophy of Science 71(5): 880–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, Kristina. 2006. The bias paradox in feminist standpoint epistemology. Episteme 3(1–2): 125–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, Kristina. 2009. Scientific knowledge: A stakeholder theory. In The social sciences and democracy, ed. J. van Bouwel, 62–80. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, Kristina. 2010. Diversity and dissent in the social sciences: The case of organization studies. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, published online september 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schickore, Jutta. 2008. Doing science, writing science. Philosophy of Science 75(3): 323–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Tara. 2004. “Social” objectivity and the objectivity of values. In Science, values, and objectivity, ed. Peter Machamer and Gereon Wolters, 143–171. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam. 2001. Social empiricism. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam. 2006. Groupthink versus the wisdom of crowds: The social epistemology of deliberation and dissent. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 44: 28–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Miriam, and Alan Richardson. 2005. A critical context for Longino’s critical contextual empiricism. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 36: 211–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Michael. 2001. Problems of knowledge: A critical introduction to epistemology. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. Brad. 1999. A defense of Longino’s social epistemology. Philosophy of Science 66(3): 538–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, Alison. 2002. Thinking from things: Essays in the philosophy of archaeology. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, Alison. 2006. Socially naturalized norms of epistemic rationality: Aggregation and deliberation. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 44: 43–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Heidi Grasswick for detailed comments on an earlier version of the manuscript. A version of the manuscript was presented in the Second Conference of the Society for Analytical Feminism at the University of Kentucky in 2008. I wish to thank Sharon Crasnow, Nancy Daukas, Phyllis Rooney, and Miriam Solomon for their critical feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristina Rolin .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rolin, K. (2011). Contextualism in Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. In: Grasswick, H. (eds) Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-6835-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics