Skip to main content

Extended Knowledge Overextended?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Knowers and Knowledge in East-West Philosophy

Abstract

It is undeniable that computer technology has had a major impact on how we engage enquiry. We use computer devices to store information that helps us in our daily lives—just think of the contacts on your phone and whatever calendar app you might use to keep track of your schedule. Furthermore, people enjoy easy and quick access to a wide range of reliable online resources such as Nature, Reuters, and Encyclopedia Britannica through their laptops or smartphones. Powerful search engines such as Google open up the door to swaths of information, enabling people easily to acquire a wide range of true beliefs through reliable means about all kinds of subject matters. However, what is the status of such true beliefs? In particular, once beliefs cease to be occurrent, do we still have non-occurrent beliefs, and, if true and reliably sustained, do they still qualify as knowledge? If they do, we would have cases of extended belief and knowledge, as these computer devices go beyond onboard capacities such as perception and memory. However, unlike our beliefs and desires, many information-storing apps and resources do not have the capacity automatically to “update” their information in light of new information. Moreover, wouldn’t extended belief and knowledge lead to massive cognitive bloat—an unpalatable explosion of belief and knowledge completely detached from an ability naturally to recall the relevant information? It would seem so given the wide variety of storage repositories and devices (literally) at one’s fingertips (online journals, Dropbox, Google, stored telephone contacts). Doesn’t cognitive bloat threaten to undermine the notion of expertise? Is it really possible to become an expert on a given topic by simply and easily looking up information via one’s smartphone and saving it? And where, now, would we place cognitive effort—steps taken by individuals to commit details to memory, to apply knowledge, to deliberate, and to assess and reflect? In “Extended Knowledge Overextended?”, Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen and Jens Christian Bjerring offer a comprehensive discussion of extended belief and knowledge. They criticize two recent attempts to mitigate concerns about cognitive bloat by arguing that their effectiveness is contingent on the current state of technology—in particular, the fact that computer devices are currently external to us. However, if computer devices seamlessly integrated with our own onboard capacities—the so-called neuromedia—become reality, it may be much more difficult to resist extended belief and knowledge and, with them, massive cognitive bloat.

We are grateful to Davide Fassio, Jie Gao, Walter Hopp, Masashi Kasaki, Kevin Lynch, and Søren Overgaard for comments. We are likewise grateful to Karyn L. Lai for her great work as the editor of this collection. A special thanks goes to Mog Stapleton for providing feedback on an earlier version of the chapter. Her feedback prompted a substantial expansion of the introduction and considerable trimming of the other sections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For technical background, see Musk (2019)—a whitepaper on Neuralink. The full one-hour session is available at the Neuralink YouTube channel (https://youtu.be/DVvmgjBL74w).

  2. 2.

    Interview at the Code Conference in 2016 (https://youtu.be/wsixsRI-Sz4; 56:50 onward).

  3. 3.

    Interview at the Code Conference in 2016 (https://youtu.be/wsixsRI-Sz4; 58:50 onward).

  4. 4.

    Interview at the Code Conference in 2016; launch presentation livestreamed on Neuralink’s YouTube channel on July 16, 2019 (https://youtu.be/r-vbh3t7WVI).

  5. 5.

    See also Chalmers (2008), the foreword to Clark’s Supersizing the Mind (2008). Chalmers’ 2011 TEDxSydney talk was entitled “Is Your Phone Part of Your Mind?” and gives the same argument (https://youtu.be/ksasPjrYFTg). Musk has said repeatedly in interviews that we are already cyborgs—see, e.g., the interview at the Code Conference 2016 (https://youtu.be/wsixsRI-Sz4; 58:50 onward).

  6. 6.

    In Bjerring and Pedersen (2014), we talked about this consequence of the extended mind thesis in terms of restricted omniscience : a person enjoys restricted omniscience with respect to a particular, fairly specific subject matter—say, past Academy Award winners or NBA standings and statistics—if the person has complete (or close to complete) extended knowledge with respect to that subject matter.

  7. 7.

    Put differently, computer devices can result in a significant upgrade to your biological memory. Earlier we spoke of boosting memory through neuromedia, and here we say that computer devices, whether external or internal, can result in a memory upgrade. It is important to qualify this. We are not saying that human memory is small. It is widely agreed that it is huge—about 2.5 petabytes (or a million gigabytes). The totality of our memories takes up much, much more space than what is available on smartphones and other computer devices we have access to. There are many types of memories and different ways that they are stored. What we have in mind when making the upgrade-related claims is quite specific: think of how much text you can store on a regular laptop or smartphone. Now consider whether you could store all of that information and retrieve it from biological memory. Probably not. Computer memory involves an upgrade in the sense that, counting it as yours, it puts you in a position to recall many things that you would otherwise not be able to recall.

  8. 8.

    See also Rubert (2004, Sect. IV) and Sprevak (2009, Sect. V).

  9. 9.

    Interestingly, this complaint suggests the existence of an intimate connection between the qualitative and quantitative significance of cognitive extension: non-onboard capacities and resources such as notebooks and external computer devices do not support extended belief because it would imply massive cognitive bloat. A point about the quantity or scale of cognitive extension supports a substantial qualitative conclusion.

  10. 10.

    Clark and Chalmers (1998: 17). Our formulation of the three first conditions follows Clark (2010: 46). The label “trust and glue” is due to Clark.

  11. 11.

    Clark and Chalmers (1998: 17).

  12. 12.

    See, e.g., Kelp (2013), Pritchard (2010), Palermos (2011, 2014, 2015). As for examples of extended cognition, think of the game Tetris, where buttons are used to rotate figures in order to determine whether they fit into empty slots in a structure, or the task of determining the product 13 × 17 by using a calculator. According to Clark and Chalmers, the following parity principle forces a nondiscriminatory approach to internally and externally driven cognition: “If, as we confront some task, a part of the world functions as a process which, were it done in the head, we would have no hesitation in recognizing as part of the cognitive process, then that part of the world is (so we claim) part of the cognitive process” (Clark and Chalmers 1998: 8). Since we would not hesitate to take mental rotation and mental calculation as part of the cognitive process, we should not hesitate to recognize the external devices as part of the cognitive process either. Cognitive processes thus extend into the external environment.

  13. 13.

    Classic works on reliabilism include Goldman (1979, 1986). It is standard also to include a no-defeaters condition. We leave it out here for ease of exposition. However, nothing hangs on this simplification, as the arguments and considerations satisfy this type of condition or can be straightforwardly modified to do so.

  14. 14.

    Bjerring and Pedersen (2014: 27).

  15. 15.

    Bjerring and Pedersen (2014: 30).

  16. 16.

    The Lone case is like the case called “Cut and Paste” in Bjerring and Pedersen (2014: 29), except that it makes explicit the subject’s attitude toward the existence and reliability of the information-sustaining source. This added layer of explicitness will the helpful for the purposes of our discussion in Sects. 5 and 6.

  17. 17.

    Other discussions of cognitive bloat or intimately related issues include Allen-Hermanson (2013), Carter and Kallestrup (2020), Farkas (2012), Ludwig (2015), Lynch (2014, 2016), Pritchard (2010, 2018a, b, c), Smart (2012), Sprevak (2009, 2019), and Wikforss (2014). More on Wikforss (2014) and Carter and Kallestrup (2020) below.

  18. 18.

    Wikforss (2014, Sect. 3).

  19. 19.

    See, e.g., Shah and Velleman (2005).

  20. 20.

    Wikforss (2014: 469).

  21. 21.

    Wikforss (2014: 470–471).

  22. 22.

    The functional role of belief in explaining action together with desire relates to practical reasoning. As just seen, Wikforss argues that the information in Otto’s notebook is unfit to feature in practical reasoning in the way that beliefs are supposed to do. She further argues that the information in the notebook is unfit to play the role of belief in theoretical reasoning. See Wikforss (2014: 472–474).

  23. 23.

    Wikforss (2014: 475).

  24. 24.

    Pritchard (2018a: 329).

  25. 25.

    Lynch uses the term “Google knowledge” for the kind of knowledge generated through neuromedia. He is keen to emphasize that we should be critical of such knowledge and recognize its limitations—in particular, that it fails to deliver understanding. For a book-length discussion of this issue, see Lynch (2016). Pritchard likewise argues that we need to recognize the limitations of knowledge generated through external devices or neuromedia. Among other things, even if they result in swaths of knowledge, this type of knowledge does not contribute toward achievement of the chief epistemological aim of education: to build intellectual character. This aim, according to Pritchard, is a matter of cultivating and exercising onboard capacities. See Pritchard (2018a) for an extended argument to this effect. Interesting as they may be, we have relegated these observations to a footnote because what matters for present purposes is the fact that both Lynch and Pritchard grant that neuromedia sustain belief.

  26. 26.

    The answer to Lone+’s question is, of course, “Esbjerg Forenede Boldklubber”—or “EFB” for short. During the 1978–1979 season, EFB accumulated 46 points, claiming the championship with a convincing 6-point margin and a goal difference of 29 goals (59 for, 30 against). One author strongly approves of the content of this footnote—the other less so.

  27. 27.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 879).

  28. 28.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 881).

  29. 29.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 879, 881).

  30. 30.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: Sect. 2, 882).

  31. 31.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 881–882).

  32. 32.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 872, 881). See also their comments in note 18. Carter and Kallestrup’s MEMORAID case (2020: 873) involves meta-incoherence about the origin of the subject’s beliefs. We return to the MEMORAID case below.

  33. 33.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 882). In the extensive body of work on the value problem, it is widely assumed that knowledge is more valuable than any epistemic standing that falls short of knowledge. See, e.g., Carter and Jarvis (2012), Greco (2009), Kvanvig (2003), Pritchard (2007), and Pritchard et al. (2018). Greco is a prominent advocate of the idea that knowledge is a cognitive achievement (2003, 2010, 2013). Another prominent advocate is Sosa (2007). Both Greco and Sosa likewise endorse the ability intuition, that is, the idea that S’s true belief that p can only qualify as knowledge if the belief is due (at least to a considerable extent) to S’s cognitive ability. Furthermore, they take achievement and ability to be intimately related: knowledge is a cognitive achievement because it is due to ability.

  34. 34.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 880).

  35. 35.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 880). They also argue that Telo does not satisfy the condition of typical invocation (i.e. C1). We leave this aside for present purposes.

  36. 36.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 880–881).

  37. 37.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 873–874).

  38. 38.

    Carter and Kallestrup (2020: 882).

  39. 39.

    Greco (2003, 2010, 2013), Sosa (2007).

  40. 40.

    Prominent advocates of sensitivity include Dretske (1971) and Nozick (1981). Prominent advocates of safety include Pritchard (2005), Sosa (1999), and Williamson (2001).

References

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. 2013. Superdupersizing the Mind: Extended Cognition and the Persistence of Cognitive Bloat. Philosophical Studies 164: 791–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bjerring, J.C., and N.J.L.L. Pedersen. 2014. All the (Many, Many) Things We Know: Extended Knowledge. Philosophical Issues 24: 23–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J.A., and B. Jarvis. 2012. Against Swamping. Analysis 72: 690–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J.A., and J. Kallestrup. 2020. Varieties of Cognitive Integration. Noûs 54: 867–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 2008. Foreword. In Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action and Cognitive Extension, ed. A. Clark, ix–xvi. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Memento’s Revenge. In The Extended Mind, ed. R. Menary, 43–66. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58: 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1971. Conclusive Reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. 2012. Two Versions of the Extended Mind Thesis. Philosophia 40: 435–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. 1979. What Is Justified Belief? In Justification and Knowledge, ed. G. Pappas, 1–23. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. 2003. Knowledge as Credit for True Belief. In Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, ed. M. DePaul and L. Zagzebski, 111–134. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Value Problem. In Epistemic Value, ed. A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D. Pritchard, 313–321. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Achieving Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. A (Different) Virtue Epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85: 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. 2013. Extended Cognition and Robust Virtue Epistemology. Erkenntnis 78: 245–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of Knowledge. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, D. 2015. Extended Cognition and the Explosion of Knowledge. Philosophical Psychology 28: 355–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M.P. 2014. Neuromedia, Extended Knowledge and Understanding. Philosophical Issues 24: 299–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The Internet of Us: Knowing More and Understanding Less in the Age of Big Data. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musk, E. 2019. An Integrated Brain-Machine Interface Platform with Thousands of Channels. Journal of Medical Internet Research 21: e16194. https://doi.org/10.2196/16194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, O. 2011. Belief-Forming Processes, Extended. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2: 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Knowledge and Cognitive Integration. Synthese 191: 1931–1951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Active Externalism, Virtue Reliabilism and Scientific Knowledge. Synthese 192: 2955–2986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. 2005. Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Recent Work on Epistemic Value. American Philosophical Quarterly 44: 85–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Cognitive Ability and the Extended Cognition Thesis. Synthese 175: 133–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018a. Neuromedia and the Epistemology of Education. Metaphilosophy 49: 328–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018b. Extended Knowledge. In Extended Epistemology, ed. J.A. Carter, A. Clark, J. Kallestrup, O. Palermos, and D. Pritchard, 90–104. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018c. Extended Virtue Epistemology. Inquiry 61: 632–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D., J. Turri, and J.A. Carter. 2018. The Value of Knowledge. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. Zalta (Summer 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/knowledge-value/.

  • Rubert, R.D. 2004. Challenges to the Hypothesis of Extended Cognition. Journal of Philosophy 101: 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N., and D. Velleman. 2005. Doxastic Deliberation. Philosophical Review 114: 497–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, P. 2012. The Web-Extended Mind. Metaphilosophy 43: 446–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 1999. How to Defeat Opposition to Moore. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 141–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. 2009. Extended Cognition and Functionalism. Journal of Philosophy 106: 503–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Extended Cognition. In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780415249126-V049-1.

  • Wikforss, Å. 2014. Extended Belief and Extended Knowledge. Philosophical Issues 24: 460–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2001. Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pedersen, N.J.L.L., Bjerring, J.C. (2022). Extended Knowledge Overextended?. In: Lai, K.L. (eds) Knowers and Knowledge in East-West Philosophy. Palgrave Studies in Comparative East-West Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-79349-4_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics