Skip to main content

Counterfactual Conditionals in the Avian Debate: Ars Obligatoria and Possible Worlds Semantics in the Parliament of Fowls

  • Chapter
Chaucer the Alchemist

Part of the book series: The New Middle Ages ((TNMA))

  • 109 Accesses

Abstract

In the Nun’s Priest Tale, Chaucer defers to “the hooly doctour Augustyn, / Or Boece, or the Bisshop Bradwardyn” (VII.3232–3) for a detailed discussion on the topic of God’s foreknowledge. After this apparent dismissal of material that he cannot sift to the husks (NPT, VII.3238), the poet nonetheless finds it here necessary to pause for a moment to distinguish between “symple necessitee,” “free choys,” and “necessitee condicioneel.” Interestingly, Chaucer recasts the “greet disputisoun” as it relates to modal logic (NPT, VII.3238). In the poet’s own version of simple necessity, he isolates the modal adverb “Nedely,” which qualifies the copula “to doon” in the kind of modal construction “A is necessarily B” (as opposed to non-modal propositions that exclude such words as “necessarily” and “possibly”). Moreover, the far more complicated conditional necessity reads, “if A, then necessarily B.” Boethius employs conditional necessity for the argument that God’s knowledge of future events does not bridle man’s free choice.1 In this chapter, I will examine these and other such modal statements in another poem, the Parliament of Fowls. In fact, conditional “if… then…” statements and imaginative conjectures embedded in the oft-repeated word “wolde” permeate the poem’s dialogue and draw attention to the poetic potential for actualizing the possible within the reality of the inner dream.

Wheither that Goddes worthy forwityng

Streyneth me nedely for to doon a thyng—

“Nedely” clepe I symple necessitee—Or elles, if free choys be graunted me

To do that same thyng, or do it noght,

Though God forwoot it er that I was wroght;

Or if his wityng streyneth never a deel

But by necessitee condicioneel.

(Nun’s Priest Tale, VII.3243–50)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. J. A. W. Bennett, The Parlement of Foules: An Interpretation, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  2. A.J. Minnis, “The Parliament of Fowls,” in Oxford Guides to Chaucer: The Shorter Poems, ed. A.J. Minnis, V.J. Scattergood, and J. J. Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 252–322.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See also Thomas L. Reed, Middle English Debate Poetry and the Aesthetics of Irresolution (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 1990), 355.

    Google Scholar 

  4. see Derek S. Brewer, “The Genre of the Parlement of Foules,” Modern Language Review 53 (1958): 321–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Zeeman, “Philosophy in Parts: Jean de Meun, Chaucer, and Lydgate,” in Uncertain Knowledge: Scepticism, Relativism, and Doubt in the Middle Ages, ed. Dallas G. Denery II, Kantik Ghosh, and Nicolette Zeeman (Turnhout: Brepols, 2014), 234.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Hester Goodenough Gelber’s 2004 book entitled It Could Have Been Otherwise: Contingency and Necessity in Dominican Theology at Oxford, 1300–1350 (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 2004).

    Google Scholar 

  7. see also John Marenbon, Medieval Philosophy: An Historical and Philosophical Introduction (Oxon: Routledge, 2007), 321–2.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Jennifer E. Ashworth, “Logic,” in The Cambridge History of Science, Volume 2: Medieval Science, ed. David C. Lindberg and Michael Shank (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 541.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also Rodney Delasanta, “Chaucer and Strode,” CR 26 (1991): 205–18.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Howard H. Schless, Chaucer and Dante: A Revaluation (Norman, OK: Pilgrim, 1984), 94.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kathryn L. Lynch, Chaucer’s Philosophical Visions, Chaucer Studies 27 (Cambridge: D.S. Brewer, 2000), 99.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Simo Knuuttila, “Modal Logic,” in The Cambridge History of hater Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 354.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Calvin Normore, “Divine Omniscience, Omnipotence and Future Contingents: An Overview,” in Divine Omniscience and Omnipotence in Medieval Philosophy, ed. Tamar Rudavsky (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), 3–22.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  14. See also Oscar Becker, Untersuchungen über den Modalkalkül (Meisenheim am Glan: Anton Hain, 1952).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kathleen Hewitt, “‘Ther It Was First’: Dream Poetics in the Parliament of Fowls,” CR 24 (1989): 21.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Derek S. Brewer, “The Parliament of Fowls: Community and Conflict,” in A New Introduction to Chaucer (London: Longman, 1998), 137.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Piero Boitani, “Old Books Brought to Life in Dreams,” in The Cambridge Companion to Chaucer, ed. Piero Boitani and Jill Mann (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 69.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Robert R. Edwards, The Dream of Chaucer: Representation and Reflection in the Early Narratives (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1989), 140.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Wolfgang Clemen, Chaucer’s Early Poetry, trans. C. A. M. Sym (London: Shenval Press, 1963), 139.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Alexander Broadie, Introduction to Medieval Logic, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 61.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Paul Vincent Spade also cites Albert of Saxony and Walter Burley: “Insolubilia,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 249n31.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Catarina Dutilh Novaes, “Medieval Obligationes as Logical Games of Consistency Maintenance,” Synthese 145 (2005): 371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Sara Uckelman, “Interactive Logic in the Middle Ages,” Logic and Logical Philosophy 21 (2012): 444.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Paul Vincent Spade, “Three Theories of Obligationes: Burley, Kilvington and Swyneshed on Counterfactual Reasoning,” History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (1982): 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Catarina Novaes, “Roger Swyneshed’s Obligationes: A Logical Game of Inference Recognition?” Synthese 151 (2006): 125–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Henrik Lagerlund and Erik Olsson, “Disputation and Change of Belief: Burley’s Theory of obligationes as a Theory of Belief Revision,” in Medieval Formal Logic: Obligations, Insolubles, and Consequences, ed. M. Yrjönsuuri (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 35–62.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  27. Christopher J. Martin, “Obligations and Liars,” in Sophisms in Medieval Logic and Grammar: Acts of the Ninth European Symposium or Medieval Logic and Semantics, held at St Andrews, June 1990, ed. Stephen Read (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 357–81.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Mikko Yrjönsuuri, “Obligations as Thought Experiments,” in Studies on the History of Logic, ed. I. Angelelli and M. Cerezo (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1996), 79–96.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Eleonore Stump, “Obligations: From the Beginning to the Early Fourteenth Century,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 318.

    Google Scholar 

  30. David Lawton, Chaucer’s Narrators (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 42.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Deanne Williams, “The Dream Visions,” in The Yale Companion to Chaucer, ed. Seith Lerer (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006), 172.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See also Paul Vincent Spade, “The Logic of Disputation in Walter Burley’s Treatise on Obligations,” Synthese 63 (1985): 355–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Ian Robinson, Chaucer and the English Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972), 61.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Russell A. Peck, “Chaucer and the Nominalist Questions,” Speculum 53 (1978): 758.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Alexander N. Gabrovsky

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gabrovsky, A.N. (2015). Counterfactual Conditionals in the Avian Debate: Ars Obligatoria and Possible Worlds Semantics in the Parliament of Fowls. In: Chaucer the Alchemist. The New Middle Ages. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137523914_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics