Skip to main content

Distributed Model-Based Science

Scientific Models Are Not Fictions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Abductive Structure of Scientific Creativity

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 37))

  • 404 Accesses

Abstract

In the current epistemological debate scientific models are not only considered as useful devices for explaining facts or discovering new entities, laws, and theories, but also rubricated under various new labels: from the classical ones, as abstract entities and idealizations, to the more recent, as fictions, surrogates, credible worlds, missing systems, make-believe, parables, functional, epistemic actions, revealing capacities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this perspective I basically agree with the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values as limpidly depicted in Steel (2010). In chapter eight I will illustrate how, in recent times, various kinds of what I call epistemic irresponsibility are precisely jeopardizing the efficiency of these “epistemic weapons”.

  2. 2.

    Suárez’s approach to scientific models as fictions is actually more sophisticated than it may appear from my few notes. Basically, Suárez does not defend the view according to which models are fictions: even if he defends the view that models contain or lead to fictional assumptions, he explicitly rejects the identification of models and fictions, preferring instead to stay “quietist” about the ontology of models, and focusing rather on modeling as an activity—see in particular his introduction to the 2009 Routledge volume he edited entitled Fictions in Science (Suárez 2009b).

  3. 3.

    I will reconsider the demarcation problem in Sect. 3.2.1 of the following chapter.

  4. 4.

    The analytic literature on scientific models has recently clearly acknowledged both the role of scientific models in extended/distributed cognition but also their related capacity to favor “understanding”. The increase of explanatory inferential ability—which favors understanding—can in turn be broken down along different dimensions of explanatory power: non-sensitivity, precision, factual accuracy, degree of integration, and cognitive salience: “The explanatory power of the model, and consequently the amount and type of understanding it can provide, amounts to the number and importance of these inferences it enables. [...] Understanding the model and understanding with the model should be kept” (Kuorikoski and Ylikoski 2015, p. 3834). Toon (2015, p. 3874) too exploits extended cognition to propose a new gracious view of the nature of understanding: “Understanding is not always in the head. Instead, it involves brain, body and world”. Finally, on the problem of degrees of understanding of phenomena and its relationship with explanationist and manipulationist interpretation cf. the rich (Kelp 2015, p. 3794).

  5. 5.

    Representational delegations are those cognitive acts that transform the natural environment in a cognitive one.

  6. 6.

    I introduced this concept in the previous chapter, Sect. 1.4.1.

  7. 7.

    An analysis of the differences between models in biology and physics and of the distinction between natural, concrete, and abstract models from a traditional epistemological perspective is illustrated in Rowbottom (2009). A comparison between experiments as commonly thought to have epistemic privilege over simulations provided by models is given by Parke (2014). The importance of the different roles played in science by thought experiments, simulations, and computer simulations is further studied in El Skaf and Imbert (2013), taking advantage of a unique conceptual framework.

  8. 8.

    Thomson-Jones (2012) too acknowledges, even if in the framework of an analytic scenario, not indebted to cognitive science, the importance of “concrete” models, and establishes a novel and useful distinction between mathematical and non-mathematical models together with the concept of “propositional model”.

  9. 9.

    The semiotic (iconic) status of models—in general—has also been extensively acknowledged by the recent analytic literature, cf. for example Kralemann and Lattmann (2013), who amply illustrate a Peircean-based approach. As also observed by the authors, the semiotic theory of models seems to contribute to the solution of the “ontological puzzle” of models.

  10. 10.

    Actually the concept is much more complicated also illustrating its relationship with abductive cognition and cognitive niches. .

  11. 11.

    The complicated analysis of some seminal Peircean philosophical considerations concerning abduction (which refers to all the cognitive processes that lead to hypotheses), perception, inference, and instinct, which I consider are still important to current cognitive and epistemological research, is provided in Magnani (2009, Chap. 5).

  12. 12.

    A detailed treatment of this issue is given in the article “Vision, thinking, and model-based inferences” Raftopoulos (2017), published in the Handbook of Model-Based Science (Magnani and Bertolotti (2017)).

  13. 13.

    On the puzzling problem of the “modal” and “amodal” character of the human brain processing of perceptual information, and the asseveration of the importance of grounded cognition, cf. Barsalou (2008a, b).

  14. 14.

    “The basic argument for common coding is an adaptive one, where organisms are considered to be fundamentally action systems. In this view, sensory and cognitive systems evolved to support action, and they are therefore dynamically coupled to action systems in ways that help organisms act quickly and appropriately. Common coding, and the resultant replication of external movements in body coordinates, provides one form of highly efficient coupling. Since both biological and nonbiological movements are equally important to the organism, and the two movements interact in unpredictable ways, it is beneficial to replicate both types of movements in body coordinates, so that efficient responses can be generated” Chandrasekharan (2009, p. 1069): in this quoted paper the reader can find a rich reference to the recent literature on embodied cognition and common coding.

  15. 15.

    Written natural languages are intertwined with iconic aspects too. Stjernfelt  (2007) provides a full analysis of the role of icons and diagrams in Peircean philosophical and semiotic approach, also taking into account the Husserlian tradition of phenomenology.

  16. 16.

    In a perspective that does not take into account the results of cognitive science but instead adopts the narrative/literary framework about models as make-believe, Toon (2010) too recognizes the role of external models in perturbing mental models to favor imagination: “Without taking a stance in the debate over proper names in fiction, I think we may use Walton’s analysis to provide an account of our prepared description and equation of motion. We saw [...] that these are not straightforward descriptions of the bouncing spring. Nevertheless, I believe, they do represent the spring, in Walton’s sense: they represent the spring by prescribing imaginings about it. When we put forward our prepared description and equation of motion, I think, those who are familiar with the process of theoretical modelling understand that they are to imagine certain things about the bouncing spring. Specifically, they are required to imagine that the bob is a point mass, that the spring exerts a linear restoring force, and so on” (p. 306).

  17. 17.

    It is not surprising to find in recent analytic academic articles about models in science the reference to the concept of imagination: for example Levy nicely stresses that modeling is not only the representation of target phenomena, but is also intimately linked to the imagination, “[...] we utilize the imagination as a means of describing and reasoning about a real-world object. [...] models are imaginative descriptions of real-world phenomena” (Levy 2015, pp. 791 and 797). Also Meynell (2014, p. 4149) stresses the imaginative role of those particular kinds of models that are the thought experiments.

  18. 18.

    On ignorance and epistemic irresponsibility see Chap. 8, Sect. 8.5.

References

  • Barsalou, L. W. (2008a). Cognitive and neural contributions to understanding the conceptual system. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 17(2):91–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (2008b). Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59:617–645.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolotti, T. (2012). From mindless modeling to scientific models. The case of emerging models. In Magnani, L. and Li, P., editors, Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Western and Eastern Studies, pages 75–104, Heidelberg/Berlin. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2011). How scientific models can explain. Synthese, 1:33–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009a). If no capacities then no credible worlds. But can models reveal capacities? Erkenntnis, 70:45–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R. (2009b). Models: Parables v. fables. Insights, 1(8):2–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2010). Informational versus functional theories of scientific representation. Synthese, 172:197–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekharan, S. (2009). Building to discover: A common coding model. Cognitive Science, 33:1059–1086.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2007). Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 74:48–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2010). Scientific models and fictional objects. Synthese, 172:215–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H. and De Smedt, J. (2011). Mathematical symbols as epistemic actions. Synthese, 190/1:3–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • El Skaf, R. and Imbert, C. (2013). Unfolding in the empirical sciences: Experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese, 190(16):3451–3474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2012). Selective ignorance and agricultural research. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 38(3):328–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against Method. Verso, London-New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (2009). Fictionalism. In Suárez, M., editor, Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pages 36–19. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2010). Keeping quiet on the ontology of models. Synthese, 172:231–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010a). Fiction and scientific representation. In Frigg, R. and Hunter, M. C., editors, Beyond Mimesis and Nominalism: Representation in Art and Science, pages 97–138, Heidelberg/Berlin. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010b). Fiction in science. In Woods, J., editor, Fictions and Models: New Essays, pages 247–287. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010c). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172:251–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2007). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172:269–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2009). Why scientific models should not be regarded as works of fiction. In Suárez, M., editor, Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pages 248–258, London. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21:725–740.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies, 143:101–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, L. J. (2013). Selective ignorance and multiple scales in biology: Deciding on criteria for model utility. Biological Theory, 8(1):74–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34:503–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1999). Cognitive artifacts. In Wilson, R. A. and Keil, F. C., editors, Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences, pages 126–7. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2015). Understanding phenomena. Synthese, 192(12):3799–3816.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. and Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive Science, 18:513–549.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kralemann, B. and Lattmann, C. (2013). Models as icons: Modeling models in the semiotic framework of Peirce’s theory of signs. Synthese, 190(16):3397–3420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. and Lehtinen, A. (2009). Incredible worlds, credible results. Erkenntnis, 70:119–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. and Ylikoski, P. (2015). External representations and scientific understanding. Synthese, 192(12):3817–3837.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2015). Modeling without models. Philosophical Studies, 172(3):781–798.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2004a). Conjectures and manipulations. Computational modeling and the extra-theoretical dimension of scientific discovery. Minds and Machines, 14:507–537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2004b). Model-based and manipulative abduction in science. Foundations of science, 9:219–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. and Bertolotti, T., editors (2017). Handbook of Model-Based Science. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009). MISSing the world. Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70:29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2014). Imagination and insight: A new account of the content of thought experiments. Synthese, 191(17):4149–4168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2011). Idealizations and scientific understanding. Philosophical Studies, 160/2:237–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naylor, R. (1976). Real experiment and didactic demonstration. Isis, 67(3):398–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. and Chandradekharan, S. (2009). Hybrid analogies in conceptual innovation in science. Cognitive Systems Research, 10(3):178–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1999). Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. General Scholium [1726]. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA. Third edition, translated by I. B. Cohen and A. Whitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2012). Abduction and estimation in animals. Foundations of science, 17(4):321–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2017). Abduction in Context. The Conjectural Dynamics of Scientific Reasoning. Springer, Switzerland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parke, E. C. (2014). Experiments, simulations, and epistemic privilege. Philosophy of Science, 81(4):516–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. vols. 1-6, Hartshorne, C. and Weiss, P., eds.; vols. 7-8, Burks, A. W., ed.

    Google Scholar 

  • Portides, D. P. (2007). The relation between idealization and approximation in scientific model construction. Science & Education, 16:699–724.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2017). Vision, thinking, and model-based inferences. In Magnani, L. and Bertolotti, T., editors, Handbook of Model-Based Science, pages 573–604. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, A. (1966). Non-Standard Analysis. North Holland, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. P. (2009). Models in biology and physics: What’s the difference. Foundations of Science, 14:281–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2010). Epistemic values and the argument from inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 77:14–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology. An Investigation on the Borderlines of Phenomenology, Ontology, and Semiotics. Springer, Berlin/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2009a). Scientific fictions as rules of inference. In Suárez, M., editor, Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pages 158–178. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M., editor (2009b). Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Fictions, inference, and realism. In Woods, J., editor, Fictions and Models: New Essays, pages 225–245. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7:1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 70:3–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2010). Missing systems and the face value practice. Synthese, 172:283–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2012). Modeling without mathematics. Philosophy of Science, 79(5):761–772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2010). The ontology of theoretical modelling: Models as make-believe. Synthese, 172:301–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2015). Where is the understanding? Synthese, 192(12):3859–3875.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M. (2010). The theoretician’s gambits: Scientific representations, their formats and content. In Magnani, L., Carnielli, W., and Pizzi, C., editors, Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Abduction, Logic, and Computational Discovery, pages 533–558, Heidelberg/Berlin. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealizations. Journal of Philosophy, 104(12):639–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1925). Science and the Modern World. Lowell Lectures, 1925. Macmillan, New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., editor (2010). Fictions and Models: New Essays. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. and Rosales, A. (2010a). Unifying the fictional. In Woods, J., editor, Fictions and Models: New Essays, pages 345–388. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. and Rosales, A. (2010b). Virtuous distortion. Abstraction and idealization in model-based science. In Magnani, L., Carnielli, W., and Pizzi, C., editors, Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Abduction, Logic, and Computational Discovery, pages 3–30, Heidelberg/Berlin. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Magnani .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Magnani, L. (2017). Distributed Model-Based Science. In: The Abductive Structure of Scientific Creativity. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 37. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-59256-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics