Skip to main content

The Constitution of Responsibility: Toward an Ordonomic Framework for Interpreting (Corporate Social) Responsibility in Different Social Settings

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Order Ethics: An Ethical Framework for the Social Market Economy

Abstract

This article shows how taking a constitutional economics perspective can clarify the idea of responsibility. Applying constitutional economics, the authors distinguish between within-game (or sub-constitutional) responsibility when playing a game and context-of-game (or constitutional) responsibility for developing the conditions under which a game will be played. These two conditions are interpreted as comprising not only the institutions (rules of the game) but also discourse about the game, its deficiencies, and reform options. Accordingly, the authors’ concept of “ordo-responsibility” distinguishes between “governance responsibility” and “discourse responsibility.” This concept is used to critically discuss the conventional dichotomy between state and non-state actors. The authors examine the capacity of private actors to engage in political processes of rule-setting and rule-finding. The article thus provides important conceptual clarification for the debate on corporate social responsibility.

The authors thank two anonymous reviewers as well as the editor for constructive and very valuable comments. The authors also thank participants of the 2006 conference “Business Ethics, Social Integration and Corporate Citizenship” in Valencia, Spain, for comments on a conference paper that first developed some of the ideas of this article and that has been published as Beckmann and Pies (2008) in the according conference volume.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For example, in soccer, the duration of the game could be changed from 90 to 60 min, the number of players could be changed from 11 to 5, or off-side positions could be made legal. Any such change in rules would basically result in a different game. The constitutional perspective takes this second level of choice into consideration.

  2. 2.

    There is a long tradition in ethics according to which it is wrong to hold someone responsible for something the person cannot influence. This idea can be traced back to the Roman Corpus Iuris Civilis. At around 100 A.D., Aulus Celsus Cornelius wrote in the Digest (50, 17, 185): “Impossibilium nulla obligatio est.” Cf. Spruit (2001, p. 985). However, the classical Latin expression of this idea that nobody is bound beyond ability is much better known: ultra posse nemo obligatur (to say one should implies one can).

  3. 3.

    From this perspective, the given preferences do not refer to normal market goods but to “commodities” or “basic goods” such as “health,” “the good life,” etc. (cf. Becker 1996). Consequently, this approach does not look at a “preference” for, say, aspirin, but instead treats aspirin (its existence, its effects, its price, etc.) as one of the constraints that channel how rational actors try to best satisfy their desire for the basic good “health.” If a rational actor learned about a new and better drug than aspirin and therefore changed his or her medication, the rational-choice perspective would not treat this as a case of transformed preferences but as a change in behavior triggered by altered information constraints.

  4. 4.

    By this logic, even rational actors with strictly given meta-preferences have an interest in participating in discourse in order to learn about and adapt to the social constraints and interdependencies that determine the possibility space of their behavior. This is of particular importance when it comes to addressing the collective self-harm in a social dilemma. To overcome a social dilemma through collective action, the actors need to know how the others perceive and evaluate the situation. Here, it makes a huge difference whether the actors interpret their situation as one of pure conflict—a zero-sum game—or as a precarious positive-sum game (cf. Schelling 1980, 2006). To be sure, from a rational-choice perspective, discourse alone may be insufficient to solve a social dilemma, but far from simply being “cheap talk,” discourse can help facilitate an agreement to (re-)form institutional incentives in a mutually advantageous way.

References

  • Aaronson, S.A. 2011. Limited partnership: Business, government, civil society, and the public in the extractive industries transparency initiative (EITI). Public Administration and Development 31: 50–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu, D., and J.A. Robinson. 2006. Economic origins of dictatorship and democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. 1984. The evolution of cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W.J. 1975. Business responsibility and economic behavior. In Altruism, morality, and economic theory, ed. E.S. Phelps, 45–56. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W.J., and S.A.B. Blackman. 1991. Perfect markets and easy virtue: Business ethics and the invisible hand. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. 1976. The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. 1993. Nobel lecture: The economic way of looking at behavior. Journal of Political Economy 101(3): 385–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G.S. 1996. Accounting for tastes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckmann, M. 2010. Ordnungsverantwortung. Rational-Choice als ordonomisches Forschungsprogramm [Ordo-responsibility. Rational choice as an ordonomic research program]. Berlin, Germany: Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckmann, M., and Pies, I. 2008. Ordo-responsibility. Conceptual reflections towards a semantic innovation. In Corporate citizenship, contractarianism and ethical theory, eds. J. Conill, C. Luetge, and T. Schönwälder-Kuntze, 87–115. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckmann, M., S. Hielscher, and I. Pies. 2014. Commitment strategies for sustainability: How business firms can transform trade-offs into win-win outcomes. Business Strategy and the Environment 23:18–37. doi: 10.1002/bse.1758.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J.R. 1999. Does business ethics rest on a mistake? Business Ethics Quarterly 9: 583–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J.R. 2011. The implications of the new governance for corporate governance. In Corporate citizenship and new governance: The political role of corporations, ed. I. Pies, and P. Koslowski, 133–146. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. 2004. Microeconomics. Behaviors, institutions, and evolution. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., and J.M. Buchanan. 1985. The reason of rules: Constitutional political economy. London, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M. 1987. The constitution of economic policy. American Economic Review 77: 243–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M. 1990. The domain of constitutional economics. Constitutional Political Economy 1: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M., and G. Tullock. 1962. The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J.M., Tollison, R.D., and Tullock, G. 1980. Toward a theory of the rent-seeking society. College Station, TX: Texas A & M University Economics Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J.S. 1990. Foundations of social theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, A., D. Matten, and J. Moon. 2008. Corporations and citizenship. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deitelhoff, N. 2009. The discursive process of legalization: Charting islands of persuasion in the ICC case. International Organization 63: 33–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denzau, A.T., and D.C. North. 1994. Shared mental models: Ideologies and institutions. Kyklos 47: 3–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. 1957. An economic theory of democracy. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. 2001. Legitimacy and economy in deliberative democracy. Political Theory 29: 651–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, M., and S. Zadek. 2003. Governing the provision of global goods: The role and legitimacy of nonstate actors. In Providing global public goods, ed. I. Kaul, P. Conceição, K. Le Goulven, and R.U. Mendoza, 200–224. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Eigen, P. 2006. Fighting corruption in a global economy: Transparency initiatives in the oil and gas industry. Houston Journal of International Law 29: 327–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. 1986. The market and the forum: Three varieties of political theory. In Foundations of social choice theory, ed. J. Elster, and A. Hylland, 103–132. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankel, C. 1955. The case for modern man. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter A. 1984. Collective and corporate responsibility. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frenkel, S.J., and D. Scott. 2002. Compliance, collaboration, and codes of labor practice: The Adidas connection. California Management Review 45: 29–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1962. Capitalism and freedom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1970. The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine, September 13, 32–33, 122–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. 2003. Deliberative democracy and international labor standards. Governance 16: 51–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1996. Between facts and norms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1998. Three normative models of democracy. In The inclusion of the other. Studies in political theory, pp. 239–252. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, R.B., and T.K. Biersteker (eds.). 2002. The emergence of private authority in global governance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science 162: 1243–1248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J. 2004. A market failures approach to business ethics. In The invisible hand and the common good, ed. B. Hodgson, 69–89. Berlin, Germany: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, D. 2001. Misguided virtue. False notions of corporate social responsibility. Wellington, New Zealand: New Zealand Business Roundtable.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillman, A.J., G.D. Keim, and D. Schuler. 2004. Corporate political activity: A review and research agenda. Journal of Management 30: 837–857.

    Google Scholar 

  • Homann, K. 2002. Wettbewerb und Moral [Competition and morality]. In Vorteile und Anreize [Advantages and incentives], 23–44, Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck (Original work published 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M.C. 2001. Value maximization, stakeholder theory, and the corporate objective function. Journal of Applied Corporate Finance 14: 8–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 1984. The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age (trans: Hans Jonas and David Herr). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press (Original work published in 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky (eds.). 2000. Choices, values, and frames. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, A.A., and M.J. Lenox. 2000. Industry self-regulation without sanctions: The chemical industry’s responsible care program. Academy of Management Journal 43(4): 698–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kobrin, S.J. 2009. Private political authority and public responsibility: Transnational politics, transnational firms and human rights. Business Ethics Quarterly 19: 349–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.M. 1990. Corporate culture and economic theory. In Perspectives on positive political economy, ed. J.E. Alt, and K.A. Shepsle, 90–143. Cambridge: UK Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. 1978. The methodology of scientific research programmes: Philosophical papers, vol. 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, D.R., and H. Raiffa. 1957. Games and decisions. New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. 1980. Gesellschaftliche Struktur und semantische Tradition (Societal structure and semantic tradition). In Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik: Studien zur Wissenssoziologie der modernen Gesellschaft. Vol. 1, 9–71. Frankfurt a.M, Germany: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. 1981. Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik: Studien zur Wissenssoziologie der modernen Gesellschaft. Vol. 2 [Societal structure and semantics: Studies on the knowledge sociology of modern society]. Frankfurt a.M, Germany: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. 1997. Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft [The society of society]. Frankfurt a.M., Germany: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. 1998. Modernity in contemporary society. Observations on Modernity, 1–22. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J.D., and J.P. Walsh. 2003. Misery loves companies: Rethinking social initiatives by business. Administrative Science Quarterly 48: 268–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matten, Dirk, and A. Crane. 2005. Corporate citizenship: Toward an extended theoretical conceptualization. Academy of Management Review 30: 166–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. 1968. Social theory and social structure. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Möller, H.-G. 2006. Luhmann explained: From souls to systems. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mukerji, N., and C. Luetge. 2014. Responsibility, Order Ethics, and Group Agency. ARSP. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie. 100(2): 176–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nalebuff, B.J., and A.M. Brandenburger. 1996. Co-opetition. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D.C. 1990. Institutions, institutional change, and economic performance. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • North, D.C. 1994. Economic performance through time. American Economic Review 84: 359–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • North, D.C. 2005. Understanding the process of economic change. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. 2000. Power and prosperity. Outgrowing communist and capitalist dictatorships. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oosterhout, H. v. 2005. Corporate citizenship: An idea whose time has not yet come. Academy of Management Review 30(4): 677–681.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. 1990. Governing the commons. The evolution of institutions for collective action. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Palazzo, G., and A.G. Scherer. 2006. Corporate legitimacy as deliberation: A communicative framework. Journal of Business Ethics 66: 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pattberg, P. 2005. The institutionalization of private governance: How business and nonprofit organizations agree on transnational rules. Governance 18: 589–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, Philip. 2007. Responsibility incorporated. Ethics 117: 171–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pies, I., S. Hielscher, and M. Beckmann. 2009. Moral commitments and the societal role of business: An ordonomic approach to corporate citizenship. Business Ethics Quarterly 19(3): 375–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pies, I., M. Beckmann, and S. Hielscher. 2010. Value creation, management competencies, and global corporate citizenship: An ordonomic approach to business ethics in the age of globalization. Journal of Business Ethics 94: 265–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pies, I., M. Beckmann, and S. Hielscher. 2011. Competitive markets, corporate firms, and new governance—An ordonomic conceptualization. In Corporate citizenship and new governance: The political role of corporations, ed. I. Pies, and P. Koslowski, 171–188. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pies, I., M. Beckmann, and S. Hielscher. 2013. The political role of the business firm: An ordonomic concept of corporate citizenship developed in comparison with the Aristotelian idea of individual citizenship. Business and Society. doi:10.1177/0007650313483484.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1966. The autonomy of sociology. In The open society and its enemies. Vol. 2: Hegel and Marx, 89–99. New York: Harper (Original work published 1945).

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1972. Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. 2000. The concept of responsibility—An essay in semantic analysis. In The just (trans: by David Pellauer), 11–35. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press (Original work published 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, T. 2000. “Let’s argue!”: Communicative action in world politics. International Organization 54(1): 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risse, T. 2004. Global governance and communicative action. Government and Opposition 39(2): 288–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T.C. 1980. The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA and London, UK: Harvard University Press (Original work published 1960).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T.C. 2006. Strategies of commitment and other essays. Cambridge, MA, London, UK: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A.G., and G. Palazzo. 2007. Toward a political conception of corporate responsibility: Business and society seen from a Habermasian perspective. Academy of Management Review 32: 1096–1120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A.G., and G. Palazzo. 2011. The new political role of business in a globalized world: A review of a new perspective on CSR and its implications for the firm, governance, and democracy. Journal of Management Studies 48: 899–931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A.G., G. Palazzo, and D. Baumann. 2006. Global rules and private actors: Toward a new role of the transnational corporation in global governance. Business Ethics Quarterly 16: 505–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A.G., G. Palazzo, and D. Matten. 2009. Introduction to the special issue: Globalization as a challenge for business responsibilities. Business Ethics Quarterly 19: 327–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J.A. 2000. Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. Introduction by R. Swedberg, London, UK: Routledge (Original work published 1942).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shell, G.R. 2004. Make the rules or your rivals will. New York: Crown Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shleifer, A., and R.W. Vishny. 1999. The grabbing hand. Government pathologies and their cures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1955. A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics 69(1): 99–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1976). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations, eds. by R.H. Campell and A.S. Skinner. London, UK: Oxford University Press (Original work published 1776).

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1983. Nationalism and social theory. British Journal of Sociology 34: 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spruit, J.E. (ed.). 2001. Corpus Iuris Civilis, VI, Digesten 43-50 [Body of civil law, collection]. Zutphen, The Netherlands: Walburg Pers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler, G.J., and G.S. Becker. 1977. De gustibus non est disputandum. American Economic Review 67(2): 76–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundaram, A.K., and A.C. Inkpen. 2004. The corporate objective revisited. Organization Science 15: 350–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. 1989. The economics of special privilege and rent-seeking. Boston, MA: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O.E. 1985. The economic institutions of capitalism. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O.E. 2009. Transaction cost economics: The natural progression. http://nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/economics/laureates/2009/williamson_lecture.pdf. Accessed 10 April 2013.

  • Wintrobe, R. 1998. The political economy of dictatorship. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, K.D. 2008. Emerging patters of global governance: The new interplay between the state, business and civil society. In Handbook of research on global corporate citizenship, eds. A.G. Scherer and G. Palazzo, 225–248. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus Beckmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Beckmann, M., Pies, I. (2016). The Constitution of Responsibility: Toward an Ordonomic Framework for Interpreting (Corporate Social) Responsibility in Different Social Settings. In: Luetge, C., Mukerji, N. (eds) Order Ethics: An Ethical Framework for the Social Market Economy . Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33151-5_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics