Skip to main content

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS))

  • 175 Accesses

Abstract

Among the philosophical approaches to explanation in the biological and biomedical sciences, the so-called mechanistic approach has doubtless been the subject of the widest, most lively debate. The inevitably incomplete account presented in this chapter will be confined to some of the main philosophical issues addressed, some of the most successful views put forward, and their possible impact on the approach to debating mechanisms in the health sciences, their epistemic import and the limits of the mechanistic approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Salmon (1984, 1989, 1998).

  2. 2.

    For an extended account, see, e.g., Andersen (2014a, b), Craver and Tabery (2015), Glennan and Illari (2017). I will here be concerned only with epistemological issues. On the metaphysics of mechanisms, see, e.g., Matthews and Tabery (2017), Krickel (2018).

  3. 3.

    On activities, see e.g., Machamer (2004).

  4. 4.

    On different ways to conceive of relations between macro- and micro-level explanations, see, for instance, Garfinkel (1981), Sober (1999), Weber and Van Bouwel (2002), Marchionni (2008), Ylikoski (2012).

  5. 5.

    See e.g., Craver and Bechtel (2007).

  6. 6.

    We will consider Woodward’s view extensively in Chap. 7.

  7. 7.

    See e.g., Darden and Craver (2013), esp. chs. 8 and 9.

  8. 8.

    For instance, the structural decomposition of the cell, with the identification of its component parts (mitochondrion, cytoplasm, matrix, …) has historically occurred, by means of electronic microscope, long before its functional understanding, i.e., long before the three main operations of cellular respiration were localized and understood. See Machamer et al. (2000).

  9. 9.

    That explanations in terms of “lower-level” mechanisms are not a self-evident improvement in explanatory knowledge has been argued, e.g., by Kuorikoski and Ylikoski (2010), giving the example of explanations in neuroeconomics. The authors argue that each explanation finds its own level by embracing a contrastive, what-if-things-had-been-different, account of explanation. We will get back to this perspective in Chap. 7.

  10. 10.

    The controversial ideas, for instance, of informational and non-informational processes, and their roles in biology, have been discussed also in works by authors directly embracing a neo-mechanist perspective, such as Jim Bogen and Peter Machamer (2011).

  11. 11.

    See Bapteste and Dupré (2013), Nicholson and Dupré (2018), Dupré and Nicholson (2018).

  12. 12.

    Standard microbial evolutionary biology is taken by Bapteste and Dupré (2013) as a field in which a processual ontology can prove particularly suitable.

  13. 13.

    Paul Thagard too has maintained that “biochemical pathways are a kind of mechanism. […] In biochemical pathways, the entities are the molecules and the activities are the chemical reactions that transform a molecule into other molecules” (Thagard, 2002, pp. 237–238, italics added).

  14. 14.

    Ioannidis and Psillos (2017) support their view considering apoptosis, its regulatory role in the organism, and the two signaling pathways (intrinsic and extrinsic) through which it can occur.

  15. 15.

    This appears for instance in: Giovannetti et al. (2013), Kimball, Jefferson (2006), Nethi et al. (2015), Wang and Gu (2016), Nosrati et al. (2017).

  16. 16.

    Obviously, if the pathway is composed of only one step, then the direct function and the final function coincide.

  17. 17.

    Another example of the same molecule having two different final functions insofar as it belongs to two different pathways is provided by the SCF, a growth factor. See Boniolo and Lanfrancone (2016). On the role of biomarkers in establishing causal pathways, see e.g., Vineis and Perera (2007).

  18. 18.

    See, e.g,, Meyer et al. (2011).

  19. 19.

    This point will be addressed in greater detail in Chap. 5.

  20. 20.

    A perspectival flavor is also held to characterize the attribution of functions to mechanisms. Craver, e.g., maintains that his account of functional descriptions is ineliminably perspectival insofar as what an observer decides and/or what her interests in a given object of investigation are is taken to matter in the assessment of functions (Craver, 2013).

  21. 21.

    “ExplanationsONTIC (i.e., things in the world) have no normative dimensions, yet the full success of all explanationsC/T/C depends upon meeting an ontic norm of getting things right (in conjunction with meeting highly variable, epistemic success conditions). ExplanationsONTIC are held to be always explanatory, since it is held that they just do account for phenomena. What is “good” as explanatoryC/T/C practice is held to ultimately bottom out in what is true. I refer to this as the thesis of the normative priority of ontic norms over epistemic norms” (Sheredos, 2016, p. 925).

  22. 22.

    On this see for instance Bokulich (2016).

  23. 23.

    See Craver and Kaplan (2020). See also O’Malley et al. (2014): “building more of everything into the model does not automatically augment knowledge” (p. 818).

  24. 24.

    See also Kästner (2018).

References

  • Andersen, H. (2014a). A field guide to mechanisms: Part I. Philosophy Compass, 9(4), 274–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H. (2014b). A field guide to mechanisms: Part II. Philosophy Compass, 9(4), 284–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bapteste, E., & Dupré, J. (2013). Towards a processual microbial ontology. Biology and Philosophy, 28, 379–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J., & Machamer, P. (2011). Mechanistic information and causal continuity. In P. Illari, F. Russo, & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the sciences. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2016). Fiction as a vehicle for truth: Moving beyond the ontic conception. The Monist, 99, 260–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo, G., & Campaner, R. (2018). Molecular pathways and the contextual explanation of molecular functions. Biology and Philosophy, 33, 24. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9634-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo, G., & Lanfrancone, L. (2016). Decomposing biological complexity into a conjunction of theorems. The case of the Melanoma Network. Humana.Mente – Journal of Philosophical Studies, 30, 19–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., Pemberton, J., & Wieten, S. (2020). Mechanism, laws and explanations. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 10(25), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Functions: Selection and mechanisms (pp. 133–168). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2014). The ontic account of scientific explanation. In M. I. Kaiser et al. (Eds.), Explanation in the special sciences: The case of biology and history (pp. 27–52). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Kaplan, D. (2020). Are more details better? On the norms of completeness for mechanistic explanation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71, 287–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Tabery, J. (2015). Mechanisms in science. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/science-mechanisms/

  • Dammann, O. (2020). Etiological explanations. Illness causation theory. CRC Press, Taylor & Francis Group.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75, 958–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2013). In search of mechanisms. The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2013). Living causes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary, LXXX VII, 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J., & Nicholson, D. (2018). A manifesto for a processual philosophy. In D. Nicholson & J. Dupré (Eds.), Everything flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology (pp. 3–42). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Forge, J. (1993). How should we explain remote correlations? Philosophica, 51(1), 83–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin-Hall, L. (2016). New mechanistic explanation and the need for explanatory constraints. In K. Aizawa & C. Gillett (Eds.), Scientific composition and metaphysical ground (pp. 41–74). Palgrave MacMillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giovannetti, E., et al. (2013). Molecular mechanisms and modulation of key pathways underlying the synergistic interaction of Sorafenib with Erlotinib in non-small-cell-lung cancer (NSCLC) cells. Current Pharmaceutical Design, 19, 927–939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S., & Illari, P. (Eds.). (2017). The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Integrating the ontic and epistemic. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 237–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis, S., & Psillos, S. (2017). In defense of methodological mechanism: The case of apoptosis. Axiomathes, 27, 6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, M. R. (2019). Sleep and inflammation: Partners in sickness and in health. Nature Reviews Immunology, 19(11), 702–715. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41577-019-0190-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kästner, L. (2018). Integrating mechanistic explanations through epistemic perspectives (pp. 68–79). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimball, S. R., & Jefferson, L. S. (2006). Signaling pathways and molecular mechanisms through which branched-chain amino acids mediate translational control of protein synthesis. The Journal of Nutrition, 136(1), 227S–231S. https://doi.org/10.1093/jn/136.1.227S

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1996). Philosophical foundations of the social sciences. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (2002). Explaining inequality. In B. Phillips, H. Kincaid, & T. J. Scheff (Eds.), Towards a sociological imagination (pp. 131–148). University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krickel, B. (2018). The mechanical world. The metaphysical commitments of the new mechanistic approach. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, K., & Ylikoski, P. (2010). Explanatory relevance across disciplinary boundaries – The case of neuroeconomics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 17, 219–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, J., & Dewhurst, J. (2021). The mechanistic stance. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 11, 20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 27–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2001). Explanatory unification: Double and doubtful. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 31(4), 488–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marchionni, C. (2008). Explanatory pluralism and complementarity, from autonomy to integration. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 38, 314–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, L., & Tabery, J. (2017). Mechanisms and the metaphysics of causation. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, U., Feldon, J., & Dammann, O. (2011). Schizophrenia and autism: Both shared and disorder-specific pathogenensis via perinatal inflammation? Pediatric Research, 69(5), 26R–33R.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nethi, S. K., et al. (2015). Investigation of molecular mechanisms and regulatory pathways of pro-angiogenic nanorods. Nanoscale, 7(21), 9760–9770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D., & Dupré, J. (2018). Everything flows. Towards a processual philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nosrati, N., et al. (2017). Molecular mechanisms and pathways as targets for cancer prevention and progression with dietary compounds. International Journal of Molecular Sciences, 18, 2050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M., et al. (2014). Multilevel research strategies and biological systems. Philosophy of Science, 81, 811–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2018). Making mechanism interesting. Synthese, 195, 11–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. N. (2018). Causal concepts in biology: How pathways differ from mechanisms and why it matters. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(1), 131–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, XII) (pp. 3–219). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1998). Causality and explanation. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sheredos, J. (2016). Re-reconciling the epistemic and ontic views of explanation (or, why the ontic view cannot support norms of generality). Erkenntnis, 81(5), 919–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skipper, R. A. (1999). Selection and the extent of explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 66, S196–S209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1999). The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 542–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2002). Pathways to biomedical discovery. Philosophy of Science, 70, 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eck, D. (2015). Reconciling ontic and epistemic constraints on mechanistic explanation, epistemically. Axiomathes, 25(1), 5–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vineis, P., & Perera, F. (2007). Molecular epidemiology and biomarkers in etiologic cancer research: The new in light of the old. Cancer Epidemiology, Biomarkers and Prevention, 16, 1954–1965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, D., & Gu, J. (2016). Integrative clustering methods of multi-omics data for molecule-based cancer classification. Quantitative Biology, 4, 58–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & van Bouwel, J. (2002). Can we dispense with structural explanations of social facts? Economics and Philosophy, 18, 259–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2015). The ontic conception of scientific explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 54, 20–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Mechanisms and psychological explanation. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science (pp. 31–79). Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P. (2012). Micro, macro, and mechanisms. In H. Kincaid (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of social science (pp. 21–45). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachariae, R. (2009). Psychoneuroimmunology: A bio-psycho-social approach to health and disease. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 50(6), 645–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zachariae, R. (2020). Social relations and health. In J. Sholl & S. Rattan (Eds.), Explaining health across the sciences (pp. 383–403). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Campaner, R. (2022). Processes, Mechanisms, and Mechanistic Models. In: Explaining Disease: Philosophical Reflections on Medical Research and Clinical Practice. European Studies in Philosophy of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-05883-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics