I. Introduction

The key aim of this paper is to augment Gabriel Gottlieb’s objection to Dryfus’s claim that concepts are not operative in expert’s unreflective actionsFootnote 1 [9]. I argue that expert’s testimony, about neither being aware of reasons nor recalling reasons behind his actions, is insufficient to prove that concepts or reasons are inoperative when he is acting ‘in the zone’ [8]. I suggest that being unaware of reasons, behind one's actions in the zone, could likely be a consequence of his minimized reflections on his maximized or expert level concepts. Moreover, not recalling every reason behind one's actions could be a consequence of his maximum concentration on processing and coordination of his activity, as opposed to committing his finite mental capacities to memorizing the reasons behind his step-by-step actions, when he is in the zone.

To achieve these goals, I begin with a summary of Dryfus’s claim that the phenomenon of embodied coping reveals that expert actions are primarily unreflective. According to Dryfus, an expert is at his best when he is acting in the flow, which does not involve mental representations, planning, or conceptual activity. Dryfus argues that in unreflective actions, embodied skills and know-how perform the role of reflection, but agrees that conceptuality operates in the actions of novices. Additionally, I review McDowell’s opposing assertions that mature embodied coping is permeated with conceptual mindedness, and that one's perceptions and actions are conceptual all the way down [6].

After outlining McDowell-Dryfus's debate, I provide a synopsis of Gottlieb’s position that practical concepts and unreflective intelligence in lieu of perceptual concepts operate in one's unreflective actions, contrary to Dreyfus’s view.

Finally, I supplement Gottlieb’s position on unreflective action, which points out that the fact that agents fail to notice or seem unaware of concepts when acting in the zone, is insufficient proof for the claim that concepts are inoperative at this level of action. I offer additional reinforcement to defend the conceptuality of one's seemingly unreflective actions by arguing that:

(i) Concepts that an agent develops over time with practice, starting from the stage of novelty, become deeply rooted and persist in his expertise stage. It is against common sense to accept that expert’s rooted concepts disappear just when he puts them to work in action.

(ii) All else equal, the strengths of an agent’s concepts and concentration are inversely proportional to intensity of his reflections. For example, a novice athlete, with under-developed concepts and weaker concentration skills, need to reflect more intensely on more concepts when he plays in a game. Conversely, an expert athlete, with stronger concepts and sharper concentration, may find minimal reflections on his strengthened concepts sufficient to compete. An expert mentally conditions himself to expend his finite and available mental capital to attain optimal performance and results for a given task. Such expert level mental conditioning involves leveraging strength of his concepts and sharpening his concentration on the activity and its goals as opposed to remembering every reasons for his step-by-step actions, which may otherwise require only his minimum reflections. Therefore an agent’s minimized reflections may be a more plausible culprit for how he may neither notice nor recall detailed reasons behind his actions in flow. Dryfus claims that when experts are in the flow, thinking about actions would degrade their performance from expert level to competency, and thus concepts have no use in expert’s flow activities [8]. Dryfus holds that only after concepts and reasoning are relinquished, then one's expertise can return to his activity. However, as noted earlier, an expert’s reflections and concentration modulate from minimum to maximum depending on the task's performance requirement and its difficulty. Therefore, while maximally concentrating on the task at hand, I suggest that an expert could minimally reflect on his strong concepts, because minimal reflections may simply be sufficient when things are going well, not because concepts are disruptive or inoperative or have no use in actions in the flow.

(iii) An expert and observer testimony about use of concepts to strategize and review actions before, during, and after the game, supports the operation of conceptual and yet seemingly unreflective actions.

(iv) And, there are alternative conceptual-friendly explanations for the examples Dryfus offers including Knoblauch's emotions such as anxiety, worry, or loss of confidence, which could have gotten in the way of his game, and not Knoblauch's reasoning and concepts which Dryfus assume to have ruined his game and flow.

II. Discussions

A. Summary of McDowell-Dryfus Debate and Gottlieb’s Objections, with Emphasis on Unreflective Actions

(i) Dryfus's View:

Dryfus asserts that McDowell would be committing the myth of mental by “presuming that a linguistic and conceptual deconstruction of any clear divide between ‘mind and world’ teaches us that perception is conceptual all the way out”. He disagrees with the claim that “actions are conceptual all the way down”, and that our “embodied coping is permeated with mindedness” [11]-[13][18]. Dryfus claims that we have non-conceptual, non-propositional, non-rational, and non-mental embodied coping skills, some of which we share with pre-linguistic infants and higher order animals [5][6]. He states that much of our encounters with the world is in total absorption by way of embodied coping, when we cease to be a subject altogetherFootnote 2 [7]. Moreover, when we are in flow “there is no experience of an object and so no object to bring under a conceptFootnote 3” [15][16].

Following Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty phenomenological positions, Dryfus holds that we have the capacity to engage in many complex or simple embodied actions when we get ‘in the zone’ where we can skillfully respond to our world without thinking [15]. When we are in the zone, affordances and solicitations, mindlessly draw us into embodied copings and actions - without the operation of conceptsFootnote 4. In practice, Dryfus views mindedness as the enemy of embodied copingFootnote 5. We plan beforehand and initiate, but when we are in the zone of the activity, we do not experience an ego doing itFootnote 6. In skillful mindless coping, we are at our best, when we unreflectively get absorbed in a space that solicits a certain activityFootnote 7. Dryfus uses the example of a blitz chess player who operate in speedy as ‘in the zone’ type actions, when he has no time to think [5]. Dryfus sees the chess player as one who does not think but just respond to the patterns on the board; and being drawn to act, the chess player does what needs to be done. According to Dryfus, we engage the world by way of our skillful body, responding to affordances in a certain way and by reacting to solicitations, such as pulling our arm towards the doorknob and not the coffee mug, move the bishop and not the queen, throw a curve-ball and not to second base [8]. Our bodily skillfulness responds to our surroundings as a field of “meaningfully configured situations that solicit some responses and repels others, and our bodily comportments are attuned to these solicitations” [8]. Dryfus holds that to gain status of expert (skill) perceiver or agent, one does not involve the internalization of such concepts or reflection, but instead short-circuit them by “developing a direct bodily responsiveness to the overall configuration of a situation” [6].

In order to retain our freedom from the casual world and keep our agnatic spontaneity, Dryfus argues that in absorbed mindless coping, we are free because we choose to respond, to being bound or not, in the flow activityFootnote 8 [8]. Our second nature, acquired from socio-cultural practices is nature too, and our expressions of our second nature in unreflective bodily coping is not a brutal causal eventFootnote 9 [15].

We have the capacity to interrupt our bodily absorption in the flow, which enables us to step back and reflect, and then our self-consciousness reemerges. Our consciousness may be called into action, if our mind detects something has gone wrongFootnote 10 [5][7]. When we are absorbed in everyday skillful coping we may well have the capacity to step back and reflect, but we may not be able to exercise that capacity without disrupting our coping [8]. Dryfus posits that reflecting and monitoring what we are doing as we are doing it, leads to a performance that is at best competent, and only after abandoning monitoring our activity, can we regain our expertise.

In summary, for Dryfus where actions are concerned, there are two separate ways of being open to the world—the conceptual and the non-conceptual way. “The conceptual way in its pure form describes what happens when one confronts a difficult situation, steps back, figures out what to do, and then responds competently” [8]. But, in so far as “one is an expert in any domain and when things are going well (when he is in the zone), one responds directly and transparently to the situation’s demands mindlessly” and he remains free to choose to be bound in the zone or free himself from it, at all times [9].

(ii) McDowell’s Views:

McDowell asserts that for mature people, embodied coping is permeated by mindedness [12]. He contends that mindedness is operative in our unreflective concepts and actions, and this is not incongruent with our immersed bodily lifeFootnote 11. McDowell argues that our perception, thoughts, and action can only be smooth because our perceptual relation to the world is conceptual all the way out. He reads the “phenomenology of embodied coping as supporting his recasting of rationality as thoroughly embodied, and suggests that it is Dreyfus who is clinging to a detached conception of rationality” [18]. McDowell objects to Dryfus’s suggestion that mindedness is detached from our immersed bodily life, because that would be committing to a kind dualism vulnerable to the Myth of the Disembodied IntellectFootnote 12 [11]. McDowell also objects to Dryfus claiming that man, in one hand, is free and open to bind himself to the affordances and solicitations in the zone, and on the other hand he is free to step-back from his activities in the zone and reflect on reasons and concepts [7]. McDowell implies that such discontinuous characterization, of our actions in and out of the zone, resembles a “disembodied intellect” [12].

Concepts and our capacity for conceptualization are operative whether or not we are conscious of them. When a chess, baseball, or tennis player starts thinking, “then acting is not the basic action and player loses because his means-end rationality tries to takes over, but it cannot do as good of a job as his skills in controlling bodily movementsFootnote 13” [11].

For McDowell, affordances and solicitations are the same once they are made explicit, and both belong to the space of reason. When we learn how to ride a bike, the training wheels don’t become invisible. Similarly, McDowell does not agree with cognitivists who claim that when we become experts, our rules become unconscious [12]. Both McDowell and Dryfus agree that “thanks to socialization, experts conform to reasons that can be retroactively reconstructed” [5]. However, McDowell claims that reasons are not behind action but are in action such as in unreflective ones including the case of phronesisFootnote 14 [5]. Unreflective actions are neither detached nor discursive [11]. For the case of phronesis, unreflective action is a case of properly formed practical intellect at work.

Dryfus implies that McDowell is afraid that without conceptuality, unreflective actions will not fit in McDowell’s space of reason. McDowell objects to Dryfus trying to forced fit unreflective action to be determined by disenchanted causal interaction.

Consequential part of the Dryfus-McDowell debate hinges on how unreflective bodily coping or actions are conceptual, and how actions are permeated with rationality and mindedness. McDowell holds that, while in the phenomenology of unreflective actions, there may be an appearance of no reasoning, but there is responsiveness to reasons and rationalityFootnote 15 [11]. This is because, in our process of our upbringing (Buildung) we are initiated into tradition and language and inculcated into culture, when we acquire our second nature and habits of a distinctively rational form. He states that “The ability of adult humans to step back, means that the same conceptual capacities must be shaping experience, whether the subject is unreflectively immersed in action or not. The capacities that are operative in ordinary perceptual engagement with the world, and in ordinary bodily action, belong to a subject’s rationality in that strong sense: "they are conceptual in the sense in which I claim that our perceptual and active lives are conceptually shaped” [12].

In summary, McDowell rejects the idea of existence of non-conceptual experiences [11]. He claims that our conceptual content and capacities are already operational in our experiencing the world, and because there is spontaneity in conceptual capacities, our experience is open to the world.

Zahavi characterizes spontaneity as a reflective capacity and argues that “for McDowell, only a self-conscious subject, a subject capable of self-ascribing experiences, can have awareness of an objective world”. On McDowell’s understanding it is consequently “the spontaneity of the understanding, the power of conceptual thinking, that brings both the world and the self into view” [11]. Therefore, for McDowell “creatures without conceptual capacities consequently lack both self-consciousness and experience of objective reality” [16].

However, McDowell reading of Knoblauch example, emphasizes on the capacity to reflect notwithstanding, suggests that he may be open to the idea that being able to act skillfully requires temporarily quieting down the ability to reflect [12].

(iii) Review of Gabriel Gottlieb’s (2011) paper over McDowell-Dryfus debate:

Gottlieb focused on whether embodied coping in speedy action is conceptually shaped. He objects to Dryfus by claiming that in speedy actions such as blitz chess, or baseball one's reflection may drop out, but that does not by itself prove absence of conceptualityFootnote 16, Footnote 17, Footnote 18, Footnote 19. Gottlieb objects to Dryfus for failing to defend linking why if an action involves concepts, then it must involves reflection. His strategy is to “undermine Dreyfus’s general assumption by arguing that perceptual concepts (e.g. my chess pieces are white) can contribute to perceptual experiences independent of reflection” via our practical concepts, such as moving the kingFootnote 20 [9]. Gottlieb agrees with Sellars that at least when it comes to perceptual concepts, conceptual inferential activity required for experience becomes - through habit and learning - a form of non-reflective intelligence that operates at an unconscious levelFootnote 21 [17]. The result is that thought, action, and experience are conceptual, having the structure of judgments, but without the conscious activity of comparison and analysisFootnote 22.

To respond, Dryfus could shift the burden of proof to Gottlieb in that practical concepts are vulnerable to the similar kinds of challenge as perceptual concepts, since experts do not report any reflection or experience of practical concepts. Moreover, the existence and distinction of practical concepts from perceptual concepts cannot be taken for granted and needs to be substantiated. Although Dryfus agrees that practical wisdom enables one to do things intelligently, Dryfus notes that such things are done without explicit thought or concepts, as in the case of Aristotle’s phronesisFootnote 23[8]. Hence, Gottlieb could counter Dryfus by arguing that practical concepts and unreflective intelligence are operative in our unreflective actions, similar to the case of phronesisFootnote 24.

In summary, Gottlieb posits that “for an action to be informed by concepts, it does not require explicit reflection during the experience”. Gottlieb concedes that Dreyfus might be right that “at certain levels in the development of skills, reflection on different practical concepts might be needed, and that it is possible in some cases for this act of reflection to eventually drop out”. However, he asserts that when our reflections drop out, “this does not necessarily mean that our practical concepts drop out” [9]. Also, Dryfus, shifting the burden of proof on conceptualists, does not prove that concepts are not operative for experts in the zone of actions, and Gottlieb throws the same burden of proof back to Dryfus.

B. Supplementing Gottlieb’s Objection to Dryfus

So far, I have outlined Dryfus’s position that one's conceptual capacities are available and operative sometimes but not pervasive in his flow activities. McDowell position is that one's perceptions and actions are conceptual all the way down. To prove his point, Dryfus argues in part that concepts must not be operative if agents do not experience them in the flow activity. Because expert’s phenomenological reports suggest that concepts are not noticed in speedy actions or in flow, and because of the evidence that reflections on concepts interfere with one's successful actions, then it is concluded that concepts are neither used nor pervasive in such activitiesFootnote 25. Gottlieb agrees with MacDowell's view that experts not noticing concepts do not automatically prove that they are not used, because unreflective actions can be guided by expert’s practical concepts or unreflective intelligence.

In the proceeding section, by expanding on the phenomenology of agent’s actions including the before-during-after flow experience, I aim to supplement Gottlieb’s defense of conceptuality of unreflective actions.

To achieve this goal, I would argue that (i) Concepts grow, take root, and carry over throughout agent’s development stages, from novelty to expertise. It seems against common sense to accept that such rooted concepts disappear or to imply that they should take a back seat in the unconscious or subconscious, just when the expert puts them to work in flow action. It is hard to endorse the idea that an expert is better off, if concepts vanished during action; (ii) For a given performance, an expert’s maximal strength of concepts and sharpened concentration, could demand minimal reflection on concepts. This could be a more plausible explanation, compared to Dryfus's, as to how concepts are not noticed in flow; (iii) Expert agent and observer often provide testimony about use of concepts to strategize and review actions before, during (post hoc), and after a flow action such as in a game. This supports the existence and prevalence of conceptual, despite seemingly unreflective, actions during flow action; (iv) More conceptual-friendly explanations may be available with respect to Dryfus’s examples. For Knoblauch’s case, it is more plausible that lack of emotional self-confidence caused him to lose his flow, not the interference of his concepts or reflections. Additionally, professional athletes may faintly reflect on concepts when ball is in their court, however they use the time to reflect (more noticeably) and make minor adjustments when the ball is in their opponent courts, which is also while they are in the zone.

The proceeding section contains my discussions to support Gottlieb’s defense of conceptuality of unreflective actions:

(i) Concepts Grow from Novelty and Persist in Expertise:

Dryfus has outlined five stages in the development of an agent’s skill: novice, advanced beginner, competence, proficiency, and expertise [2]. Novices learn and reflect on concepts over time to enhance their skills until they become experts. Dreyfus posits that after one has gone through the learning phase while he was being guided by concepts, then he transcends out of that stage and becomes an expert. At the expert stage, he no longer needs concepts at all, according to Dryfus. However, it is only natural for concepts to take root and become engrained in agents as they develop from novelty to expertise stages. It is against common sense to concede to the idea that expert’s rooted concepts grow and remain operative until competency, and then simply vanish from his mental operations when it is time for him to put those concepts to expert level work. Moreover, it seems arbitrary to accept the proposition that an expert is better off, if his deep rooted concepts temporarily became inoperative during his expert level action, as implied by Dryfus.

(ii) Maximal Strength of Concepts and Maximal Concentration Require Minimal Reflection:

For a given performance, the strength of expert’s concepts and concentration on task at hand is inversely proportional to the required reflections. Because a novice agent's concepts are weaker, more practice and more intense reflections are required to enhance his learning and subsequently improve his performance. Learning means being able to reflect and internalize the optimal conceptsFootnote 26 (or re-write old ones to get better at something). When an agent becomes an expert, minimal amount of incremental learning is required as he becomes more efficient at what he does. This in turn relaxes his need for incremental or additional reflections on his actions when he is in the zoneFootnote 27 (or improvement would demand minimal need for re-writing an agent’s existing concepts). Ultimately, when an expert gain stronger concepts via learning, practicing, and maturing, then minimal reflections may be sufficient for him to perform at the top of his game. This is how the strength of one’s concepts is inversely proportional to the intensity of his reflections needed for a given level of performance in the zone.

Another important aspect of expert’s functioning in the zone is ‘concentration’. When an agent concentrates on the activity and its goals, he zooms his focus on the present time.

Concentration has two dimensions: one is about concentrating on this task in the here and now, and the other is about not concentrating on any other task that is not in the here and now.

When the agent concentrates, he aims to forget regrets about the past (e.g. lost matches, missed opportunities, etc); he tries to stop worrying about the future (e.g. what if I lose? what happens after this set? and after this game? how will family matters, expenses, parent’s illness, and media questions shape-up?); and he stays in the present moment, channeling all his mental resources on the task at hand the best he can. Concentration can quiet the mind. This ability to concentrate involves severing or quieting non-essential past and future reflections (about all other non-relevant concepts). Hence, to be immersed in an activity such as being in the zone ideally requires filtering out all else that gets in the way of that flow action.

Not recalling every reason behind one's actions could also be in part a consequence of his sharpened or maximum concentration on processing and coordination of his activity as opposed to committing to memory the reason behind his step-by-step actions, especially in high-speed gamesFootnote 28. With agent’s concentration zoomed in on the task at hand and the strength of his deeply rooted concepts in his back pocket, so-to-speak, his reflections would regulate or modulate down sufficiently to the point that he can exercise his top skills and attain optimal performance.

Dryfus holds that only after concepts are relinquished, then our expertise can return to action. But, an agent’s reflections and concentration can modulate from minimum to maximum depending on the level of an agents’ skills and concepts about the task at hand. Hence, it is plausible that an expert minimally reflecting on his strengthened concepts while sharply concentrating on his action in the zone is because minimal reflections may simply be sufficient when things are going well, not because concepts are disruptive or inoperative or have no use in actions in flow.

In summary, strong or maximized concepts operating on expert actions with minimized reflections when he is maximally concentrating on what matters (i.e., serving the activity and its goal as opposed to memorizing every reasons behind every step in the game) could exculpate how experts may not notice or recall detailed reasons about their ‘in the zone’ actionsFootnote 29.

(iii) Concepts Operative Before-During-After the Flow Action such as in a Game:

Taking an expert’s testimony about his transitions from ‘entering flow’ to ‘exiting flow’ in conjunction with his ‘during flow’ perspective may shed more light about operation of concepts in one's actions in flow.

For example, people (e.g., athletes, observers, coaches, Sport TV specialists) in professional sports strategize about the game (i.e., studying their opponent past techniques, weakness, and strengths compared to their own team, competitive line up, the coach’s game plan, etc) before the game. After the game, they review various conceptual aspects of their game (e.g. player and team strategic objectives versus actual results, shortcomings, reason for bad executions of plans, their opponent winning and losing or new strategies, etc). Often, when an athlete watch his own game’s video re-plays and respond to reporters about strategies that worked or did not work for him, he offers conceptual explanation. Contrary to Dryfus's claim, preponderance of conceptual testimony offered by expert observers and athletes about in the zone actions before, during, and after makes it much more plausible that concepts were in use in the zone than not at allFootnote 30.

(iv) Knoblauch Emotions Could Have Gotten In The Way, Not His Concepts:

There are other conceptual friendly explanations for some of the examples that Dryfus has offered. Dryfus suggests that Knoblauch’s thinking too much about his game caused him to lose the ability to throw the ball effortlessly. I suggest that it is more plausible that Knoblauch emotional challenges such as loss of confidence ruined his game. Only after his emotional challenges, he started thinking about his missteps and reasoning to figure out why he was failingFootnote 31. His emotional imbalance and nervousness caused him to lose his flow, not the interference of his reasoning and rationalization.

Dryfus also suggests that expert’s conceptualization cannot be behind the throwing, and if it is, then it can only interfere with the absorbed copingFootnote 32. Earlier I argued that experts’ minimal reflection and their strong concepts may not interfere with their absorbed coping and can still be operative. For example, professional athletes may faintly reflect on and not notice concepts when the ball is in their own side of the court, however many athletes testify that they use the time to reflect more noticeably and make minor adjustments when ball is in their opponent side of the court. A tennis player monitors his opponent’s bodily posture and direction of his racket to anticipate the trajectory of his opponent’s next move.

III. Conclusion

In summary the goal of my paper is to supplement Gottlieb’s objection to Dryfus’s claim that concepts are not operative in expert’s unreflective actions. To achieve this goal, I first argued that it is against common sense to accept that expert’s rooted concepts become inoperative just when it is time for him to put them to work, and that his actions become entirely unreflective when he is in the zone. For example, it may seem that we open a door without thinking. But we may think about how many steps we need to take towards the door depending on how far we are from the door. We also may think about how we might use our hands and which keys to use depending on if the doorknob is keyed, lever, or circular type. An expert tennis player may not think deeply about his move when the ball is in his court, but he does think and anticipate a possible trajectory of the ball when the ball is in his opponent’s court, and plan his move depending on his opponent’s posture and racket movement. A blitz chess player may not think when it is his turn to make his move, possibly because he had some time (albeit short) to think a little bit and adjust his strategy if needed while the opponent was making his move. Therefore, using some of Dryfus’s own example, we can show that some thinking and some reflection albeit minimally may be at work, even when we are in the zone. Second, I argued that the strengths of an agent’s concepts and his concentration are inversely proportional to the intensity of his reflections. Therefore an expert’s minimized reflections may be a more plausible reason for how experts, with maximal strength of concepts and sharpened concentration, may neither notice nor recall all reasons behind their actions in flow. Third, I suggested that expert (i.e., agent and observer) testimony about use of concepts to strategize and review actions before, during, and after a game, supports conceptual and yet seemingly unreflective actions, even in flow.

Acknowledgement

I would like to express my sincere gratitude to Professor Mohammad Azadpur at San Francisco State University for his mentorship and invaluable feedbacks.