Skip to main content
Log in

What is the point of urban justice? Access to human space

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Acta Politica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Do we need a theory of urban justice? If so, what desiderata would such a theory have to meet? This paper makes a programmatic point, namely, that urban justice is a field of political philosophy in its own right, and that the recognition-theoretical approach is capable of expressing what is at stake there. A revised version of Axel Honneth’s theory of recognition meets the three desiderata of a theory of urban justice: relationality, spatiality and diversity. Whereas justice-related questions on the domestic level typically refer to the basic structure of society—concerning issues of basic rights and wealth distribution—on the city level such questions are concentrated mainly on the way urban space is organized. Ultimately, what is at stake is to articulate a vision of the city as an embodiment of human space; a space that is structured in such a way that it meets the demands for recognition. The paper tests if the framework is capable of expressing the key moral challenges of two justice-related issues of contemporary cities, namely, segregation and gentrification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This conception of human space is quintessentially moral in nature given that it involves normative standards of recognition that it must live up to. Hence this is a fundamentally different concept of space than the phenomenology of space that Henry Lefebvre has developed and that has inspired a lot of theorists who write about cities (Purcell 2002). According to Lefebvre’s descriptive claims, space ought to be understood in terms of a dialectical triad consisting of “perceived space,” “conceived space,” and “lived space”. Space is at the same time “objectively” perceived, conceptually envisioned (maps etc.), as well as experienced and shaped by those who inhabit it (Lefebvre 1991). The only way that normativity gets introduced here is through the notion that people should have a right to control the production of space that they live in, namely in order to fit their needs (Lefebvre 1996). But we cannot simply leave such power to produce space to the citizens of cities or neighborhoods themselves in the false hope that a legitimate decision will magically appear if we only let “the people” decide (see beginning of “Urban justice as access to human space” section).

  2. This lack of an empirically testable explanatory account of capitalist economies makes the recognition-theoretical approach a compromised framework for articulating the claims of the protests against capitalist globalization. As Zurn puts it: “The causes of the dislocations are to be found in variables specific to the global political economy: currency rates; disproportionate supply and demand; asymmetrical regulatory environments; capital flows; stratified availability of technologies; differential natural resources; diverse interest rates: differential regimes of private property; and so on. This means that recognition-based remedies will likely be simply ineffective against the root problems” (2015, p. 144). According to Zurn and others, Fraser’s theory might allow for such a framework, but her sketchy remarks on the dynamics of capitalism are far removed from an adequate account of the current state of global capitalism (Zurn 2015, p. 153; Thomson 2006, p. 117).

  3. Such policies can only be institutionalized provided that government agencies have sufficient political power, which shows that there is no inherent incompatibility between “power” and “recognition.” In fact, the act of recognition always presupposes a certain measure of control. As I have argued before, the logic of a theory of recognition entails an actor and corresponding moral responsibility.

  4. Margaret Kohn presents this point of view, without actually agreeing with it. Although she does believe that the choice to keep on living in an inner-city neighborhood that one cannot really afford, is basically an “expensive choice,” she argues that being threatened with eviction as a result of gentrification is still morally wrong because of “bad price luck,” a notion she borrows from Gerald Cohen. The fact that the market is responsible for the expensive nature of the taste entails that the person is not responsible for it (2016, p. 98). This strikes me as a reductionist way to argue against displacement; reductionist because it relies, I think dubiously, on the logic of autonomy-respect.

References

  • Anderson, Elisabeth. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, Rowland, and Gary Bridge (eds.). 2005a. Gentrification in a Global Context. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, Rowland, and Gary Bridge. 2005b. Introduction. In Gentrification in a Global Context, ed. Rowland Atkinson and Gary Bridge, 1–17. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, Daniel, and Avner De-Shalit. 2011. The Spirit of Cities. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, Neil, Peter Marcuse, and Margit Mayer (eds.). 2012. Cities for People, Not for Profit. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, Peter. 2003. Two Cheers for Gentrification. Howard Law Journal 46 (3): 404–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Mike. 1990. City of Quartz. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davoudi, Simin, and Derek Bell. 2016a. Understanding Justice and Fairness in and of the City. In Justice and Fairness in the City, ed. Simin Davoudi and Derek Bell, 1–20. Bristol: Policy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davoudi, Simin, and Derek Bell. 2016b. A Fairer City. In Justice and Fairness in the City, ed. Simin Davoudi and Derek Bell, 265–280. Bristol: Policy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De-Shalit, Avner. 2018. Cities and Immigration. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dikeç, Mustafa. 2001. Justice and the Spatial Imagination. Environment and Planning A 33 (10): 1785–1805.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dikeç, Mustafa. 2007. Badlands of the Republic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dikeç, Mustafa. 2009. Space, Politics and (In)justice, Justice Spatiale/Spatial Justice, 1 (September). https://www.jssj.org. Accessed 24 May 2013.

  • Dikeç, Mustafa. 2017. Urban Rage. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott-Cooper, Adam, Phil Hubbard, and Loretta Lees. 2019. Moving Beyond Marcuse, Progress in Human Geography, online early.

  • E.C. Report, 2013. Confronting Homelessness in the European Union. Brussels: European Commission.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fainstein, Susan. 2010. The Just City. London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fainstein, Susan. 2011. Redevelopment Planning and Distributive Justice in the American Metropolis. In Justice and the American Metropolis, ed. Clarissa Hayward and Todd Swanstrom, 149–175. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy. 2003. Distorted Beyond all Recognition. In Redistribution or Recognition? ed. Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, 198–236. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition?. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried, Marc. 1966. Grieving for a Lost Home. In Urban Renewal, ed. James Wilson, 359–379. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frug, Gerald. 2014. The Central-Local Relationship. Stanford Law & Policy Review 25 (1): 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frug, Gerald, and David Barron. 2008. City Bound. London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fullilove, Mindy Thompson. 2001. Root Shock. Journal of Urban Health 78 (1): 72–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaetz, Stephen, et al. 2013. The State of Homelessness in Canada 2013. Toronto: Canadian Homelessness Research Network Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, Erving. 1963. Behavior in Public Places. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, Edward. 2003. Clearing the Way. Washington: Urban Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Dan. 1990. Radin on Personhood and Rent Control. The Monist 73 (4): 642–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannerz, Ulf. 1992. Cultural Complexity. New York: Colombia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, David. 1973. Social Justice and the City. London: The University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, David. ed. 2009. The Right to the City. In Social Justice and the City, 315–333. London: The University of Georgia Press.

  • Harvey, David. 2012. Rebel Cities. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, Clarissa, and Todd Swanstrom. 2011. Introduction. In Justice and the American Metropolis, ed. Clarissa Hayward and Todd Swanstrom, 1–29. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1992. Integrity and Disrespect. Political Theory 20 (2): 187–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1997. Recognition and Moral Obligation. Social Research 64 (1): 16–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2002. Grounding Recognition. Inquiry 45 (4): 499–520.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2003. Redistribution as Recognition. In Redistribution or Recognition? ed. Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, 110–197. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. ed. 2012. Labour and Recognition. In The I in We, 56–74. Cambridge: Polity.

  • Honneth, Axel. 2014. Freedom’s Right. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, Bruce, and Jeremy Nowak. 2018. The New Localism. Washington: Brookings Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, Margaret. 2016. The Death and Life of the Urban Commonwealth. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leckie, Scott. 1989. Housing as a Human Right. Environment and Urbanization 1 (2): 90–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lees, Loretta, Tom Stater, and Elvin Wyly. 2008. Gentrification. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lees, Loretta, Tom Stater, and Elvin Wyly (eds.). 2010. The Gentrification Reader. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lefebvre, Henry. 1976. Reflections on the Politics of Space. Antipode 8 (2): 30–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lefebvre, Henry. 1991. The Production of Space. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lefebvre, Henry. ed. 1996. The Right to the City. In Writings on Cities, 63–181. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Ley, David. 1994. Gentrification and the Politics of the New Middle Class. Environment and Planning D 12 (1): 53–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lofland, Lyn. 1973. A World of Strangers. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Peter. 2000. Cities in Quarters. In A Companion to the City, ed. Gary Bridge and Sophie Watson, 270–281. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Peter. 2009. From Justice Planning to Commons Planning. In Searching for the Just City, ed. Peter Marcuse et al., 91–102. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Peter, et al. (eds.). 2009. Searching for the Just City. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The Decent Society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massey, Douglas, and Nancy Denton. 1993. American Apartheid. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McBride, Cillian. 2013. Recognition. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merry, Michael. 2013. Equality, Citizenship and Segregation. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Don. 2003. The Right to the City. New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Law Center on Homelessness and Poverty. 2015. Homelessness in America. https://www.nlchp.org/documents/Homeless_Stats_Fact_Sheet. Accessed 14 Mar 2018.

  • Nine, Cara. 2018. The Wrong of Displacement. The Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (2): 240–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novy, Johannes, and Margit Mayer. 2009. As “Just” as it Gets? In Searching for the Just City, ed. Peter Marcuse et al., 103–119. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Omidi, Maryam. 2014. Anti-Homeless Spikes are Just the Latest in ‘Defensive Urban Architecture.’ The Guardian, 12 June.

  • Patch, Jason, and Neil Brenner. 2007. Gentrification. In Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology, ed. George Ritzer. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pile, Steve. 1999. The Heterogeneity of Cities. In Unruly Cities?, ed. Steve Pile et al., 7–52. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purcell, Mark. 2002. Excavating Lefebvre. GeoJournal 58 (10): 99–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purcell, Mark. 2008. Recapturing Democracy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radin, Margaret. 1986. Residential Rent Control. Philosophy & Public Affairs 15 (4): 350–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, Jennifer. 2006. Ordinary Cities. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, Richard. 2017. The Color of Law. London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sennett, Richard. 1974. The Fall of Public Man. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelby, Tommie. 2007. Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto. Philosophy & Public Affairs 35 (2): 126–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, Georg. 1903/1969. The Metropolis and Mental Life. In Classic Essays on the Culture of Cities, ed. Richard Sennett, 47–60. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

  • Smith, Neil. 1996. The New Urban Frontier. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Neil. 2002. New Globalism, New Urbanism: Gentrification as Global Urban Strategy. Antipode 34 (3): 427–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soja, Edward. 2009. Taking Space Personally. In The Spatial Turn, ed. B. Warf and S. Arias, 11–35. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soja, Edward. 2010. Seeking Spatial Justice. London: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundstrom, Ronald. forthcoming. Just Shelter: Gentrification, Integration, and Racial Equality.

  • Taylor, Charles. 1994. The Politics of Recognition. In Multiculturalism, ed. Amy Gutmann, 25–73. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1979. Hegel and Modern Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. ed. 1985. The Diversity of Goods. In Philosophy and the Human Sciences, 230–247. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Thompson, Simon. 2006. The Political Theory of Recognition. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trappenburg, Margo. 2003. Against Segregation. The Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (3): 295–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uitermark, Justus, et al. 2007. Gentrification as a Governmental Strategy. Environment and Planning A 39 (1): 125–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • UTF Report. 1999. Towards and Urban Renaissance. Urban Task Force.

  • Van Leeuwen, Bart. 2006. Social Attachments as Conditions for the Condition of the Good Life? Philosophy & Social Criticism 32 (3): 401–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, Bart. 2007. A Formal Recognition of Social Attachments. Inquiry 50 (2): 180–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, Bart. 2018. To the Edge of the Urban Landscape: Homelessness and the Politics of Care. Political Theory 46 (4): 586–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wirth, Louis. 1938/1995. Urbanism as a Way of Life. In Metropolis, ed. Philip Kasinitz, 58–82. New York: Palgrave.

  • Young, Iris. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, Iris. 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurn, Christopher. 2003. Arguing over Participatory Parity. Philosophy Today 47 (supplement): 176–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurn, Christopher. 2015. Axel Honneth. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I want to thank the following people for reading the paper and providing me with helpful suggestions: Nir Barak, Avner de-Shalit, Arnoud Lagendijk, Michael Merry, Ronald Sundstrom, Marcel Wissenburg and two anonymous reviewers.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bart van Leeuwen.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

van Leeuwen, B. What is the point of urban justice? Access to human space. Acta Polit 57, 169–190 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1057/s41269-020-00178-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/s41269-020-00178-0

Keywords

Navigation