Skip to main content
Log in

defending interpretation

  • Research
  • Published:
European Political Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An interpretive approach to political science provides accounts of actions and practices that are interpretations of interpretations. We develop this argument using the idea of ‘situated agency’. There are many common criticisms of such an approach. This article focuses on eight: that an interpretive approach is mere common sense; that it focuses on beliefs or discourses, not actions or practices; that it ignores concepts of social structure; that it seeks to understand actions and practices, not to explain them; that it is concerned exclusively with qualitative techniques of data generation; that it must accept actors' own accounts of their beliefs; that it is insensitive to the ways in which power constitutes beliefs; and that it is incapable of producing policy-relevant knowledge. We show that the criticisms rest on both misconceptions about an interpretive approach and misplaced beliefs in the false idols of hard data and rigorous methods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A longer version of this paper first appeared in the Australian Journal of Political Science. Earlier versions were presented at the American Political Science Association Annual Conference, Chicago, 1–3 September 2004; and the Australasian Political Studies Association, University of Adelaide, 29 September–1 October 2004.

  2. Although this paper concentrates on political science, interpretive approaches are widespread across the human sciences. Useful collections include Rabinow and Sullivan (1979), Rabinow and Sullivan (1987) and Scott and Keates (2001). Much of the movement charted by these collections derives from the philosophical repudiation of positivism in the 1960s and 1970s. See Bernstein (1976) and Fay (1975).

  3. See Foucault (1972, 1980). For varied assessments of the continuing impact of structuralism upon poststructuralism see Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982), Gutting (1989) and Harland (1988).

  4. When we follow the logic of disaggregating concepts like voting or policy network, we end up with micro-level stories of individual actions based on one person's set of beliefs. Although such stories are interesting as cases, there are times when we want to tell more general stories, for example about governance. To do so, we need aggregate concepts like tradition and dilemma.

  5. That said, we could make sense of someone's beliefs only by postulating them as a web that exhibits some kind of consistency and rationality. For discussion of various principles of charity according to which we do thus ascribe some kind of conceptual priority to rational beliefs see Bevir (1999: 158–171), Davidson (1984b) and McGinn (1977).

  6. We would draw attention, more generally, to the difficulties that confront any dualism of ‘scheme’ and ‘content’, or ‘paradigm’ and ‘experience’, given the implausibility of an uninterpreted reality (see Davidson, 1984a). Such difficulties affect even those who emphasise meanings only to conceive of them as schemes, paradigms, or frames, including, for example, Rein and Schon (1995).

  7. There is an extensive literature that explicitly applies an interpretive approach to policy analysis. Examples include Healy (1986), Hummel (1991), Jennings (1987), Van Eeten et al (1996), Weick (1995) and Yanow (1999).

  8. For details of our own preferred epistemology see Bevir (1999: 78–126).

References

  • Bang, H. and Sørensen, E. (1999) ‘The everyday maker: a new challenge to democratic governance’, Administrative Theory and Praxis 21: 225–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P. and Luckman, T. (1971) The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, S. (2001) ‘Ideas, norms and culture in political analysis’, Comparative Politics 33: 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. (1976) The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bevir, M. (1999) The Logic of the History of Ideas, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bevir, M. and Rhodes, R.A.W. (2003) Interpreting British Governance, London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, V. (2002) ‘On some problems with weak intentionalism for intellectual history’, History and Theory 41: 198–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burchell, G., Gordon, C. and Miller, P. (eds.) (1991) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980) Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984a) ‘On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme’, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 183–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984b) ‘Radical Interpretation’, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 125–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowding, K. (2004) ‘Interpretation, truth and investigation’, British Journal of Politics and International Relations 6: 136–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. and Rabinow, P. (1982) Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fay, B. (1975) Social Theory and Political Practice, London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (2001) ‘Taking stock: the constructivist research program in international relations and comparative politics’, Annual Review of Political Science 4: 391–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. and LePore, E. (1992) Holism: A Shopper's Guide, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1972) The Archaeology of Knowledge, translated by A Sheridan-Smith, London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980) C. Gordon (ed.) Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977, Brighton: Harvester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerring, J. (1999) ‘Does ideology matter? a roll-call analysis of key congressional votes, 1833–1992’, Journal of Policy History 11: 399–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutting, G. (1989) Michel Foucault's Archaeology of Scientific Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harland, R. (1988) Superstructuralism: The Philosophy of Structuralism and Poststructuralism, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hay, C. (2000) Political Analysis, Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healy, P. (1986) ‘Interpretive policy inquiry: a response to the limitations of the received view’, Policy Sciences 19: 381–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hummel, R.P. (1991) ‘Stories managers tell: why they are as valid as science’, Public Administration Review 51: 31–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, B. (1987) ‘Interpretation and the practice of policy analysis’, in F. Fischer and J. Forester (eds.) Confronting Values in Policy Analysis, Newbury Park, CA: Sage, pp. 128–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kass, H. and Catron, B. (eds.) (1990) Images and Identities in Public Administration, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, R. (2002) ‘Ideas, institutions, and political order: explaining political change’, American Political Science Review 96: 697–712.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAnulla, S. (2004) ‘Paving the rhodes to post-positivism? a critique of the new interpretive approach to British politics – towards a realist alternative’, paper presented to the 54th Annual Conference of the UK Political Studies Association, University of Lincoln, 6–8 April.

  • March, J.G. and Olsen, J.P. (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics, New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1977) ‘Charity, interpretation, and belief’, Journal of Philosophy 74: 521–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinow, P. and Sullivan, W. (eds.) (1979) Interpretive Social Science, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabinow, P. and Sullivan, W. (eds.) (1987) Interpretive Social Science: A Second Look, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reckwitz, A. (2002) ‘The constraining power of cultural schemes and the liberal model of beliefs’, History of Human Sciences 15: 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rein, M. (1973) Social Science and Public Policy, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rein, M. and Schon, D. (1995) Frame Reflection, New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roe, E. (1994) Narrative Policy Analysis, Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz-Shea, P. and Yanow, D. (2002) ‘“Reading”, “Methods”, “Texts”: How research methods texts construct political science’, Political Research Quarterly 55: 457–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, J. and Keates, D. (eds.) (2001) Schools of Thought: Twenty Five Years of Interpretive Social Science, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1971) ‘Interpretation and the sciences of man’, Review of Metaphysics 25: 3–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Eeten, M.J.G., Van Twist, M.J.W. and Kalders, P.R. (1996) ‘Van een narratieve bestuurskunde naar een postmoderne beweerkunde?’ Bestuurskunde 5: 168–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weick, K.E. (1995) Sensemaking in Organizations, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (1999) Social Theory of International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1972) Philosophical Investigations, translated by G. Anscombe, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yanow, D. (1999) Conducting Interpretive Policy Analysis, Newbury Park, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bevir, M., Rhodes, R. defending interpretation. Eur Polit Sci 5, 69–83 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.eps.2210059

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.eps.2210059

Keywords

Navigation