Skip to main content
Log in

Thinking the Political in the Wake of Spinoza: Power, Affect and Imagination in the Ethics

  • Feature Article: Political Theory Revisited
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

There is currently a growing interest in the philosophy and political thought of Baruch de Spinoza (1632–1677) following many years of comparative neglect, particularly within political philosophy. The focus of this paper is Spinoza's major work, the Ethics, and its relation to his political writings. It explores Spinoza's distinctive formulations of imagination and affect and considers some of the ways in which these impact upon his political thought, specifically via his reflections upon democracy and knowledge. The discussion draws particular attention to the aporetic status of imagination and its tendency towards ambivalence. It argues that this dynamic account of imagination introduces provisionality and contingency into Spinoza's reflections upon politics that may, in turn, enrich discussions seeking to introduce an awareness of the affective resonances of communication and identification to democratic theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. All references to the Ethics in the text are taken from Curley's translation (Spinoza, 1985) and use the following abbreviations: EII (Part II of the Ethics); Def (definition); P (proposition); Dem (demonstration) Schol (scholium) and Cor (corollary). All references to Spinoza's political works are taken from Elwes's translation (Spinoza, 1951).

  2. See, in particular, the studies by Balibar (1994, 1997, 1998), Negri (1991) and Lloyd and Gatens (1999).

  3. Some writers, notably Curley (1990), have suggested that is was precisely in the TTP that Spinoza sought to present, in more popular and accessible form, the geometric arguments of the Ethics. It is crucial, therefore, to take note of the trails leading to and from the political works of his lifetime. Others, for example, Rosen (1963), McShea (1968) and Vaughan (1925) tend to view the works as more self-contained.

  4. Spinoza's English translator, Samuel Shirley, has noted that the use of the Latin term sive for or usually indicates an equivalence rather than an alternative (for which the terms vel and aut are often used. This has not prevented Spinoza's conception of substance being viewed as a form of pantheism, a deification of the world, where, most famously in Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy, this static ontological system negates all particularity and denies subjectivity historical becoming and agency.

  5. In contrast to earlier thinkers who had viewed Spinoza's concept of substance somewhat statically, German Romantic philosophers understood this active, corporeal quality of imagination as giving Spinoza's system a dynamic meaning (see Engell, 1981, 117).

  6. On the relation between Nietzsche and Spinoza, see Schacht, (1999). For discussions of Spinoza's reading of Hobbes, see Sacksteder (1980) and Frost (2005).

  7. Camille Dumoulie ‘Spinoza, or the Power of Desire’ Pli Vol, 14, 2003, p. 46.

  8. See Y. Yovel (1999, 2004). For Yovel, the conatus brings about the enhancement or empowerment of being which always unfolds in time and thus remains forever oriented toward the future. See Smith (2003) for a discussion of the conatus as empowerment.

  9. As Balibar (1997) notes, this formulation of transindividualism has important theoretical echoes in Gilbert Simondon's formulations of the process of individuation in L'individuation Psychique et Collective(Paris, Editions Aubier 1989).

  10. Spinoza distinguishes between a passion and an action. While the former are swayed by the influences of external and internal reaction, and hence increase or decrease man's affective power, an action requires that one understands the cause of any of the former passions. Thus, ‘By affect I understand affections of the Body by which the Body's power of acting is increased or diminished, aided or restrained, and at the same time, the idea of these affections. Therefore, if we can be the adequate cause of any of these affections, I understand by the Affect an action, otherwise a passion’ (EIII, Def 3).

  11. Negri's study makes a very important contribution to a materialist reading of Spinoza's philosophy and political theory. It is also informed by certain Marxist premises that seem, at times, to lead to essentialist and totalizing arguments. In his later reading of Spinoza (Negri, 1998), the argument is modified somewhat and the emphasis placed upon the precarious and fluid form of the multitude; indeed, he even notes its ‘aporetic nature’ (p. 236).

  12. Spinoza's experience of the collapse of the Republican regime of the United Provinces and the brutal murder in 1672 of the de Witt brothers contributed to this analysis. See Feuer (1963, p. 138).

  13. For further discussion, see Virno (2004, 21–26) and Montag (1999, Chapter 3).

  14. Negri (1998, p. 230, 232).

  15. Comparing himself to Hobbes, Spinoza writes ‘With regard to political theory, the difference between Hobbes and myself, which is the subject of your inquiry, consists in this, that I always preserve the natural right in its entirety, and I hold that the sovereign power in a state has right over a subject only in proportion to the excess of its power over that of a subject’ (Letter 50; Wolf, 1927).

  16. TP (IV, 2 and III,8) and Balibar (1994, 15).

  17. There is an interesting line of thought to be developed here concerning the influence of Spinoza upon Adam Smith's, as well as Hume's account of countervailing passions. This has already been initiated in Hirschman's study of the ways in which the passions were used to describe forms of commercial activity as themselves virtuous activity, thus connecting the economic concerns of C17th with the virtues of man. See The Passions and the Interests, Princeton University Press, 1977.

  18. I take this expression from Ravven (2002).

  19. See also TP (III, 2).

  20. For a commentary that emphasizes the inherent individualism of Spinoza's formulation in EIV P18 and the dangers of a collectivist reading, see Lee C Rice (1990). For an opposing position, see Matheron (1969). For a recent exploration of the theoretical difficulties generated by Spinoza's own formulation of una veluti mente, by different translations of it, and by those of commentators see Balibar (2004).

  21. Spinoza's earlier formulations in EII, Dem 7 also supports this view: ‘…if a number of Individuals so concur in one action that together they are the cause of one effect, I consider them all, to that extent, as one singular thing’. An interesting parallel with Jean Luc Nancy's idea of community as being-in-common may be noted here (Nancy, 1991). Unfortunately, its development remains outside the scope of the present discussion.

References

  • Althusser, L. (1976) ‘On Spinoza’, Essays in Self-Criticism, London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, L. (1998) ‘The Only Materialist Tradition, Part 1: Spinoza’, in W. Montag and T. Stolze (eds.) The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albiac, G. (1997) ‘The Empty Synagogue’, in W. Montag and T. Stolze (eds.) The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press, 104–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1986) De Anima (trans. and intro. Hugh Lawson-Tancred). London: Penguin.

  • Balibar, E. (1994) ‘Spinoza, The Anti-Orwell: The Fear of the Masses’, in E. Balibar (ed.) Masses, Classes, Ideas: Studies on Politics and Philosophy Before and After Marx, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balibar, E. (1996) ‘What is Man in Seventeenth Century Philosophy’, in J. Coleman (ed.) The Individual in Political Theory andPractice, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balibar, E. (1997) ‘Spinoza: From Individuality to Transindividuality’, in Mededelingen vanwege het Spinozahauis, Delft, Eburon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balibar, E. (1998) Spinoza and Politics (trans. P. Snowdon, intro. W. Montag). London: Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balibar, E. (2004) ‘Potentia multitudinis, quae una veluti mente ducitur: Spinoza on the Body Politic’, in S.H. Daniel (ed.) Current Continental and Modern Philosophy, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, A. (1999) ‘The materiality of morals: mind, body and interests in Spinoza's’, Ethics' Studia Spinozana 7: 69–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, W. (1999) Why I am not a Secularist, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, W. (2005) Pluralism, North Carolina: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curley, E. (1990) ‘Notes on a Neglected Masterpiece (II): The Theological-Political Treatise as a Prolegomenon to the Ethics’, in J.A. Cover and M. Kulstad (eds.) Central Themes in Modern Philosophy, Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1988) Spinoza: Practical Philosophy (trans. R. Hurley) San Francisco: City Lights Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1990) Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (trans. M. Joughin) New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumoulie, C. (2003) ‘Spinoza, or the power of desire’, Pli 14: 44–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engell, J. (1981) The Creative Imagination: Enlightenment to Romanticism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feuer, L.S. (1963) Spinoza and the Rise of Liberalism, Connecticut: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frost, S. (2005) ‘Hobbes and the matter of self-consciousness’, Political Theory 33(4): 495–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, S. (1972) ‘A Kind of Materialism’, in Freedom of Mind and Others Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2000) Empire, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2005) Multitude, London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G. (1994) Part of Nature: Self-Knowledge in Spinoza's Ethics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G. and Gatens, M. (1999) Collective Imaginings: Spinoza, Past and Present, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McShea, R. (1968) The Political Philosophy of Spinoza, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macherey, P. (1996) ‘The Encounter with Spinoza’, in P. Patton (ed.) Deleuze: A Critical Reader, Oxford: Blackwells.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matheron, A. (1969) Individu et communité chez Spinoza, Paris: Editions de Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montag, W. (1999) Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries, London: Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J.L. (1991) The Inoperative Community, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J.L. (1998) The Sense of the World, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negri, A. (1991) The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza's Metaphysics and Politics (trans. M. Hardt) Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negri, A. (1998) ‘Reliqua Desiderantur: A Conjecture for a Definition of the Concept of Democracy in the Final Spinoza’, in W. Montag and S. Ted (eds.) The New Spinoza, Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negri, A. (2004) ‘Subversive Spinoza: (un) contemporary variations’, Timothy S. Murphy (ed.), Manchester, Manchester Universtiy Press.

  • Ravven, H.M. (1998) ‘Spinoza's individualism reconsidered: some lessons from the treatise on god, man and his well-being’, Iyyun, The Jerusalem Quarterly 47: 265–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravven, H.M. (2002) ‘Spinoza's Rupture with Tradition — His Hints of a Jewish Modernity’, in H.M. Ravven and L.E. Goodman (eds.) Jewish Themes in Spinzoa's Philosophy, Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, L. (1990) ‘Individual and Community in Spinoza's Social Psychology’, in E. Curley and F. Moreau (eds.) Spinoza: Issues and Directions, Proceedings of the Chicago Spinoza Conference, Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, S. (1963) ‘Benedict Spinoza’, in L. Strauss and J. Cropsey (eds.) History of Political Philosophy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sacksteder, W. (1980) ‘How much Hobbes might Spinoza have read?’ Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 11: 25–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schacht, R. (1999) ‘The Spinoza–Nietzsche Problem’, in Y. Yovel (ed.) Desire and Affect: Spinoza as Psychologist, New York: Little Room Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (1997) Spinoza, Liberalism and the Question of Jewish Identity, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2003) Spinoza's Book of Life: Freedom and Redemption in the Ethics, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1951) in R.H.M.Elwes (trans. and intro.) A Theologico-Political Treatise and A Political Treatise, New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1985) Collected Works of Spinoza, Vol. 1 (ed. and trans. E. Curley). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, C.E. (1925) Studies in the History of Political Philosophy Before and After Rousseau, Vol. 1. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Virno, P. (2004) A Grammar of the Multitude, New York: Semiotext[e].

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, A. (1927) The Correspondence of Spinoza, New York: Dial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. (1996) ‘Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy’, in S. Benhabib (ed.) Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yovel, Y. (1999) ‘Transcending Mere Survival: From Conatus to Conatus Intelligendi’, in Yovel (ed.) Desire and Affect: Spinoza as Psychologist, New York: Little Room Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yovel, Y. (2004) ‘Incomplete Rationality in Spinoza's Ethics: Three basic Forms’, in Y. Yovel and G. Segal (eds.) Spinoza on Reason and the ‘Free Man’, New York: Little Room Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Williams, C. Thinking the Political in the Wake of Spinoza: Power, Affect and Imagination in the Ethics. Contemp Polit Theory 6, 349–369 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300298

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300298

Keywords

Navigation