Skip to main content
Log in

Combining ‘incompatible’ foreign policy explanations: how a realist can borrow from constructivism

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Journal of International Relations and Development Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to perspectivism, models and their explanations can be put ‘next to each other’ and can thus put one another into perspective, but they can hardly compete or, even less, be combined. The question whether such combination is allowed is demonstrated to have deep epistemological roots. Unfortunately, perspectivism easily leads to the compartmentalisation of research communities and a reduced interest in the real world. As argued here, seemingly ‘incompatible’ models or theories can be made to compete through conscious effort by the researcher, and eventually their effects may restrain or reinforce one another in specific explanations. Such combination — in this case realism borrowing from constructivism — is illustrated by an explanation of the puzzle why the German great power is cautious, while the smaller Sweden is today hawkish in relation to Russia (the Ukraine 2014 conflict). In fact, combination may help bridge the much debated ‘actor-structure’ cleavage in IR.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Figure 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The common denominator of perspectives, approaches, models and theories (used interchangeably for the purpose of the present article) is that they all have the potential for delivering explanations (more or less rigorously).

  2. Quoted from Engelbrekt (2002: 60).

  3. Allison’s volume was first published in 1971. The work of Allison and Zelikow (1999), which has the same title, is a rewritten edition, including new empirical and theoretical insights.

  4. Interestingly, Hudson’s piece, including a survey of foreign policy analysis until the time of writing, does not mention neoclassical realism (launched in 1998), which is dedicated to foreign policy explanation.

  5. According to the perspectivism of Hollis and Smith, there are ‘always two stories to tell’, one of understanding, the other of explanation (Hollis and Smith 1990: 68–91). This is true as an initial assessment, of course, but it is too early to stop inquiry here.

  6. This is not to create a new ‘-ism’. Sterling-Folker (1997) uses the terms ‘compatible’ or ‘compatibility’ in her article.

  7. Of course, compatibilism should not be an excuse for saving false theories. I will not go further into the complex issue of precisely when to consider a theory falsified, though.

  8. Cf. Schimmelfennig (2004).

  9. According to his well-known metaphor, if the house is burning, everybody will run towards the entrances, irrespective of their individualities; if it is merely overheated, some people will open a window, while others will stay calm, depending on their psychological or physiological dispositions. Explanation of their behaviour will therefore have to add a knowledge about these.

  10. Cf. Rose (1998), Wivel (2005), Rathbun (2008), Glenn (2009), or Lobell et al. (2009), among others. See already Zakaria (1992), though.

  11. There is no ‘reason why neoclassical realism cannot incorporate unit-level variables, while at the same time maintaining the causal primacy of structural pressures arising from the international level’ (Taliaferro et al. 2009: 23).

  12. Cf. also Moravscik (1999: 679) in this regard.

  13. Because all structure is environment, but not all environment is structural.

  14. Cf. also Elman (1996) or Sterling-Folker (1997: 23) regarding this view.

  15. According to Rathbun (2008), a follower of Waltz (1979), the ‘system’ explains very little foreign policy, but it has prescriptions for it. And if prescriptions are not obeyed, punishment will follow: ‘when domestic politics and ideas interfere substantially in foreign policy decisionmaking [which they should not, according to Rathbun], the system punishes states’ (Rathbun 2008: 296). Moreover, ‘the punishment will fit the crime so that we expect a direct relationship between the extent to which domestic politics and ideas come to play a role and the severity of the rebuke’ (ibid.: 311). This is historically false, though. Remaining in the analogy, many states with a favourable location have lived a ‘criminal’ life without being punished, whereas the less fortunate have not.

  16. For an effort to make realism compatible with a branch of strategic culture studies, cf. Glenn (2009).

  17. For literature systematically discussing foreign policy explanatory levels, cf. Hollis and Smith (1990) or Hill (2002), for instance. The stipulated levels vary from one author to the next.

  18. To paraphrase the title of Goldmann (1976).

  19. Not even the US during unipolarity would qualify here. For instance, the Afghanistan intervention could not be analysed without taking September 11 as the external stimulus.

  20. In the words of Dueck (quoted from Glenn 2009: 526), ‘Culture is best understood as a supplement to and not a substitute for realist theories of strategic choice. Strategic culture can certainly help to explain “deviations” from balancing behavior, but since the very concept of such deviations presumes some sort of appropriate or expected response to international conditions, it is only within a realist framework that such explanations make any sense’.

  21. Amanpour, CNN, 20 March, available at http://amanpour.blogs.cnn.com/2014/03/20/ (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  22. As here conceived, thus, there is not necessarily a military aspect or the shifting of alliance status to this strategy. On various notions of balancing, cf. Waltz (1979), Walt (1987), Pape (2005), or Kai He (2012), for instance. In any case, the effectiveness of balancing is promoted by the possession of credible military, political and economic counterweight.

  23. Amanpour, CNN, 20 March, available at http://amanpour.blogs.cnn.com/2014/03/20/ (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  24. https://twitter.com/carlbildt/status/450003920187043840 (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  25. https://carlbildt.wordpress.com/2014/03/17/starka-slutsatser-i-bryssel/ (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  26. ‘Angela Merkel: Russia “will not get away” with annexation of Crimea’, http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/ukraine/10693400/Angela-Merkel-Russia-will-not-get-away-with-annexation-of-Crimea.html (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  27. ‘Steinmeier pledges additional support for Ukraine’, Auswärtiges Amt, 22 March, 2014.

  28. ‘Crimean Crisis: All Eyes on Merkel’, http://www.spiegel.de/international/world/angela-merkel-plays-central-role-in-russia-diplomacy-over-crimea-a-956834.html (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  29. Ibid.

  30. ‘Germany’s Russian rethink: How Merkel lost faith in Putin’, http://www.reuters.com/article/2014/03/20/us-germany-russia-crisis-insight-idUSBREA2J15720140320 (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  31. http://www.thelocal.de/20140905/merkel-holds-firm-at-nato-summit-russia-ukraine-reaction-force (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  32. Jan Bo Hansen, ‘Good cop, bad cop’, Weekendavisen [Danish weekly], 5 December, 2014.

  33. http://www.bundesregierung.de/Content/EN/Artikel/2014/11_en/2014-11-17-ukraine-nach-g-20-2_en.html (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  34. As (proximate) balancing is defined above, it can take any form — military or diplomatic; diplomatic means may be used to obstruct or otherwise irritate a power asserter (Pape 2005). The main thing about the concept as stipulated here, of course, is that it is non-systemic (proximate).

  35. For a European great power of today (like France or Germany), this means the European Union, approximately. For a sole superpower, its sphere of interest being global, proximate balancing is tantamount to systemic balancing.

  36. Duffield’s formulation (1999: 218), pertaining to the first decade after the Cold War.

  37. Specifically, Germany and Russia have completed the ‘Nord Stream’ Baltic Sea gas pipeline from the Bay of Finland to Greifswald in Germany; this project has been ascribed geopolitical motives by the Baltic countries and Poland, whose roles as transit countries have been diminished by it.

  38. ‘Angela Merkel is rewriting Germany’s post-war handbook on relations with Russia’, http://qz.com/194695/angela-merkel-is-rewriting-germanys-post-war-handbook-on-relations-with-russia/ (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  39. Ibid.

  40. The following paragraphs (regarding lessons 1 and 2) are based on Mouritzen and Wivel (2012: 128–29) with the written permission of Lynne Rienner (although amended for our purpose here).

  41. It is still a valid objection, for instance, that one’s opponent is ‘not thinking in terms of history’ (Landler 2007).

  42. See also ‘Poll of German view on Crimea’, Spiegel, 19–20 March, 2014, available at http://www.spiegel.de/international/germany/bild-961711-674691.html (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  43. ‘Which War to Mention?’, http://www.economist.com/news/briefing/21599410-angela-merkel-and-her-foreign-minister-crisis-throwback-worse-times-which-war (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  44. Of course, we lack the ‘smoking gun’ at this stage of research (such as leaks from a confidential conversation between Chancellor Merkel and Foreign Minister Steinmeier).

  45. ‘We did not accept that Milosevic’s Serbia intervened militarily in other ex-Yugoslav republics by referring to the protection of people with a Serbian passport [like Russia claimed to protect Russians and Ossetians with a Russian passport in South Ossetia]. And we should remember how Hitler little more than half a century ago applied precisely this doctrine to undermine and attack significant parts of Central Europe’ (quoted from Mouritzen and Wivel 2012: 130–31). The first analogy is a positive one: ‘we’, presumably the West, should do the same as in relation to Milosevic. The second one is negative: remember how tragic consequences followed from the acquiescence in Hitler’s assertiveness; by inference, the opposite of the 1930’s appeasement policy should be practiced now.

  46. This paragraph (a) is adapted from Mouritzen and Wivel (2012: 132, with the written permission of Lynne Rienner).

  47. Author’s interview with Ann-Sofie Dahl, 20 November, 2008.

  48. In general, European states’ positionings between the US superpower and Russia have not been correlated with government ideology (Mouritzen 2006).

  49. Ibid.; interview with high-level civil servant, 19 and 20 January, 2009.

  50. http://carlbildt.wordpress.com (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  51. https://twitter.com/carlbildt/status/533634339222085632 (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  52. The possibilities for explanatory combination have been briefly mentioned in Allison and Zelikow (1999: 404), whereas they are denied by the early Allison. However, none of the volumes are sufficiently clear and consistent on this crucial point.

  53. Epistemological realism should not be mistaken for IR realism, of course.

  54. For a criticism of Wight and realism, cf. Käpylä and Mikkola (2011) based on a pragmatist theory of knowledge. The article would have benefited from an empirical illustration, though.

  55. In the view of Allison and Zelikow (1999: x) models apparently ‘channel our thinking’, whether we allow it or not.

  56. For an excellent formulation of model-neutral evidence from East Asia, cf. Goldstein (2007). This allows him to confront expectations from the power-transition theory and the institutionalist theory, respectively, with this evidence and accept that mechanisms from both theories may be at work simultaneously.

  57. Cf., for instance, the ‘luxury theory’ (Mouritzen 1997) integrating geopolitics with Coser’s (1956) sociological theory that external conflict strengthens a group’s internal cohesion. Thus, it is asserted that external conflict or danger limits the ‘luxury’ of domestic politics playing a role in foreign policy-making.

  58. An argument against the additive model of an empirical nature has been made by Fordham (2009), in my view overstating the difficulties of distinguishing between ‘internal’ and ‘external’.

  59. To round off with a ‘nerdish’ sounding deduction from the present section, a neo-classical realist must, logically, be an epistemological (ontic) realist — as must any researcher combining different levels in one explanation. A true Waltzian, sticking to systemic explanation, must not. Waltz’s theory of truth is probably instrumentalism (‘theory as an instrument’), cf. Waltz (1975: 8).

  60. Analytical eclecticism is ‘focused on seeking the best answer for a problem at any given time, on the basis of relevant insights drawn from existing theories and narratives’ (Sil and Katzenstein 2010: 16). In spite of this sensible undertaking, eclecticism has no place in the establishment phase for any given theory, of course.

  61. It is not at issue here, whether in fact attraction to the US is just a means towards balancing China. If that is the case, only proximate balancing is at work.

References

  • Allison, Graham (1971) Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis, Boston: Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allison, Graham and Philip Zelikow (1999) Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis, New York: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ash, Timothy Garton (1994) ‘Germany’s Choice’, Foreign Affairs 73(4): 65–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, Thomas (2002) ‘The Power of Memory and Memories of Power: The Cultural Parameters of German Foreign Policy-Making since 1945’, in Jan-Werner Müller ed., Memory & Power in Post-War Europe: Studies in the Presence of the Past, 76–100, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Barton J. (2000) ‘Understanding Decisionmaking, US Foreign Policy, and the Cuban Missile Crisis: A Review Essay’, International Security 25(1): 134–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, Kenneth (1962) Conflict and Defence: A General Theory, New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coser, Lewis (1956) The Functions of Social Conflict, Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dessler, David (1989) ‘What’s at Stake in the Agent — Structure Debate’, International Organization 43(3): 441–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, Karl et al (1957) Political Community and the North Atlantic Area: International Organization in the Light of Historical Experience, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dueck, Colin (2009) ‘Neoclassical Realism and the National Interest: Presidents, Domestic Politics, and Major Military Interventions’, in Steven Lobell, Norrin Ripsman and Jeffrey Taliaferro eds., Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy, 139–69, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Duffield, John (1999) ‘Political Culture and State Behavior: Why Germany Confounds Neorealism’, International Organization 53(4): 765–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elman, Colin (1996) ‘Why Not Neorealist Theory of Foreign Policy?’ Security Studies 6(1): 7–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelbrekt, Kjell (2002) Security Policy Reorientation in Peripheral Europe: A Comparative-Perspectivist Approach, Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faiola, Anthony (2014) ‘Despite reluctance at home, Merkel shifts toward tougher stance on Russia’, Washington Post, 28 March, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/europe/despite-reluctance-at-home-merkel-shifts-toward-tougher-stance-on-russia/2014/03/28/f46cb5b9-df79-43c1-a175-a38793c01f3e_story.html (accessed 10 November).

  • Fierke, Karin Marie (2002) ‘Links across the Abyss: Language and Logic in International Relations’, International Studies Quarterly 46(3): 331–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fordham, Benjamin (2009) ‘The Limits of Neoclassical Realism: Additive and Interactive Approaches to Explaining Foreign Policy Preferences’, in Steven Lobell, Norrin Ripsman and Jeffrey Taliaferro eds., Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy, 251–80, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Freyberg-Inan, Annette, Ewan Harrison and Patrick James, eds (2009) Rethinking Realism in International Relations, Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenn, John (2009) ‘Realism Versus Strategic Culture: Competition and Collaboration?’ International Studies Review 11(3): 523–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldmann, Kjell (1976) ‘The Foreign Sources of Foreign Policy: Causes, Conditions, or Inputs?’ European Journal of Political Research 4(3): 291–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, Avery (2007) ‘Power Transitions, Institutions, and China’s Rise in East Asia: Theoretical Expectations and Evidence’, Journal of Strategic Studies 30(4–5): 639–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Christopher (2002) The Changing Politics of Foreign Policy, Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollis, Martin and Steve Smith (1990) Explaining and Understanding International Relations, Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holsti, Kalevi (1989) ‘Mirror, Mirror on the Wall, Which are the Fairest Theories of All?’ International Studies Quarterly 33(3): 255–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Valerie (2005) ‘Foreign Policy Analysis: Actor-Specific Theory and the Ground of International Relations’, Foreign Policy Analysis 1(1): 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis, Darryl S. L. (2002) International Relations and the ‘Third Debate’: Postmodernism and Its Critics, Westport: Praeger Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jervis, Robert (1976) Perceptions and Misperceptions in International Politics, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kai, He (2012) ‘Undermining Adversaries: Unipolarity, Threat Perception, and Negative Balancing Strategies after the Cold War’, Security Studies 21(2): 154–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapstein, Ethan and Michael Mastanduno, eds (1999) Unipolar Politics: Realism and State Strategies after the Cold War, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Käpylä, Juha and Harri Mikkola (2011) ‘‘Getting Things Right?’: A Reconsideration of Critical Realism as a Metatheory for IR’, Journal of International Relations and Development 14(4): 401–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keohane, Robert, ed. (1986) ‘Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond’, in, Neorealism and Its Critics, 158–203, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khong, Yuen Foong (1992) Analogies at War: Korea, Munich, Dien Bien Phu, and the Vietnam Decisions of 1965, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krause, Joachim (2004) ‘Multilateralism: Behind European Views’, Washington Quarterly 27(2): 43–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landler, Mark (2007) ‘Putin prompts split in German coalition’, New York Times, 22 May, http://www.nytimes.com/2007/05/22/world/europe/22europe.html?_r=3& (accessed 10 November, 2014).

  • Lapid, Yosef (1989) ‘The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in Post-Positivist Era’, International Studies Quarterly 33(3): 235–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Jack (1989) ‘The Causes of War: A Review of Theories and Evidence’, in Philip Tetlock, Jo Husbands, Robert Jervis, Paul Stern and Charles Tilly eds., Behavior, Society, and Nuclear War Vol. 1, 209–334, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Jack (2003) ‘Political Psychology and Foreign Policy’, in David Sears, Leonie Huddy and Robert Jervis eds., Oxford Handbook of Political Psychology, 253–84, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lobell, Steven, Norrin Ripsman and Jeffrey Taliaferro, eds (2009) Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lukes, Steven (1982) ‘Perspectivism in Its Place’, in Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes eds., Rationality and Relativism, 261–305, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malici, Akan (2006) ‘Germans as Venutians: The Culture of German Foreign Policy Behavior’, Foreign Policy Analysis 2(1): 37–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mastanduno, Michael (1999–2000) ‘Economic Statecraft, Interdependence, and National Security: Agendas for Research’, Security Studies 9(1–2): 288–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, Ernest (1973) ‘Lessons’ of the Past, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravscik, Andrew (1999) ‘Is Something Rotten in the State of Denmark? Constructivism and European Integration’, Journal of European Public Policy 6(4): 669–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouritzen, Hans (1988) Finlandization: Towards a General Theory of Adaptive Politics, Aldershot: Gower (Ashgate).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouritzen, Hans (1997) External Danger and Democracy: Old Nordic Lessons and New European Challenges, Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouritzen, Hans (2006) ‘Choosing Side in the European Iraq Conflict: A Test of New Geopolitical Theory’, European Security 15(2): 137–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouritzen, Hans and Anders Wivel (2012) Explaining Foreign Policy, Boulder: Lynne Rienner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pape, Robert (2005) ‘Soft Balancing against the United States’, International Security 30(1): 7–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl R., ed. (1972) ‘Two Faces of Common Sense: An Argument for Commonsense Realism and against the Commonsense Theory of Knowledge’, in, Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, 32–106, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purdon, Mark (2014) ‘Neoclassical Realism and International Climate Change Politics: Moral Imperative and Political Constraint in International Climate Finance’, Journal of International Relations and Development 17(1): 301–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert (1988) ‘Diplomacy and Domestic Politics: The Logic of Two-Level Games’, International Organization 42(3): 427–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rathbun, Brian (2008) ‘A Rose by Any Other Name: Neoclassical Realism as the Logical and Necessary Extension of Structural Realism’, Security Studies 17(2): 294–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, Dan (1996) Crucible of Beliefs: Learning, Alliances, and World Wars, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, Gideon (1998) ‘Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy’, World Politics 51(1): 144–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimmelfennig, Frank (2004) ‘Liberal Intergovernmentalism’, in Antje Wiener and Thomas Diez eds., European Integration Theory, 75–95, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweller, Randall L. (2006) Unanswered Threats: Political Constraints on the Balance of Power, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sil, Rudra and Peter Katzenstein (2010) Beyond Paradigms: Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of World Politics, Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, J. David (1961) ‘The Level of Analysis Problem in International Relations’, World Politics 14(1): 77–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, Jack (1991) Myths of Empire: Domestic Politics and International Ambition, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stelzenmüller, Constanze (2009) ‘Germany’s Russia Question’, Foreign Affairs 88(2): 89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterling-Folker, Jennifer (1997) ‘Realist Environment, Liberal Process, and Domestic-Level Variables’, International Studies Quarterly 4(1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taliaferro, Jeffrey, Norrin Ripsman and Steven Lobell, eds (2009) ‘Introduction: Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy’, in, Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy, 1–41, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Walt, Stephen (1987) The Origins of Alliances, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, Kenneth (1975) ‘Theory of International Relations’, in Fred Greenstein and Nelson Polsby eds., International Politics: Handbook of Political Science Vol. 8 1–85, Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, Kenneth (1979) Theory of International Politics, New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, Alexander (1987) ‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory’, International Organization 41(3): 335–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiberg, Håkan (2000) ‘The Nordic Security Community: Past, Present, Future’, in Bertel Heurlin and Hans Mouritzen eds., Danish Foreign Policy Yearbook 2000, 121–39, Copenhagen: Danish Institute of International Affairs (DUPI).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight, Colin (2006) Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, Colin (2007) ‘Inside the Epistemological Cave all Bets are Off’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10(1): 40–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wivel, Anders (2005) ‘Explaining Why State X Made a Certain Move Last Tuesday: The Promises and Limitations of Realist Foreign Policy Analysis’, Journal of International Relations and Development 8(4): 355–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfers, Arnold (1962) Discord and Collaboration, Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zakaria, Fareed (1992) ‘Realism and Domestic Politics: A Review Essay’, International Security 17(1): 177–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans Mouritzen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mouritzen, H. Combining ‘incompatible’ foreign policy explanations: how a realist can borrow from constructivism. J Int Relat Dev 20, 631–658 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2016.2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2016.2

Keywords

Navigation