Skip to main content
Log in

Machiavelli reloaded: Perceptions and misperceptions of the ‘Prince of realism’

  • Introduction
  • Published:
International Politics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

This article analyses the impact and legacy of Niccolò Machiavelli’s thought in International Relations. It explores the various and contrasting interpretations that have characterized the ‘Machiavellian Moment’ in political theory and international studies, revisiting some of its fundamental concepts – such as fortuna, virtù, cose di stato – and highlighting their strong heuristic and analytical potential for International Relations. The article also serves as an Introduction to the various sections and contributions of the Special Issue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. The full passage goes as follows: ‘For the Lawes of Nature (as Justice, Equity, Modesty, Mercy, and (in summe) doing to others, as we would be done to,) of themselves, without the terrour of some Power, to cause them to be observed, are contrary to our naturall Passions, that carry us to Partiality, Pride, Revenge, and the like. And Covenants, without the Sword, are but Words, and of no strength to secure a man at all’. Cf. Hobbes (1651, p. 85).

  2. According to Hegel (2003, p. 275), the state ‘possesses the highest right in relation to individuals [die Einzelnen], whose highest duty is to be members of the state’.

  3. ‘Vous pourrez aussi voir icy, Monseigneur, comme le devoir d’un bon Prince est d’embrasser est soustenir la Religion Chrestienne, et de cercher et s’enquerir de la pure verité d’icelle, et non pas approuver ni maintenir la fausseté en la Religion comme Machiavel enseigne’ [As you can see, your Excellency, the duty of a good Prince is to support the Christian religion, and to search for and enquire into its pure truth, and not to approve or condone the falsehood in religion as Machiavelli teaches]. Cf. Gentillet (1576, pp. 2–3).

  4. Cf. Machiavelli’s (1979, p. 63) letter to Giovan Battista Soderini: ‘I believe that as Nature has given every man a different face, so she also has given each a different character and imagination. From this it follows that each man governs himself according to his particular character and imagination. And because, on the other hand, times change and the order of things always shifts, the fortunate man, the one whose wishes are completely fulfilled, is he who fits his plan of action to the times; to the contrary, the unhappy man is he who fails to match his actions to the times and to the order of things’.

References

  • Althusser, L. (1999) Machiavelli and Us. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armitage, D. (2013) Foundations of Modern International Thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (eds.) (1980) The originality of Machiavelli. In: Against the Current. Essays in the History of Ideas. New York: The Viking Press, pp. 25–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cesa, M. (ed.) (2014) Introduction. In: Machiavelli on International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–31.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Croce, B. (1949) Una questione che forse non si chiuderà mai. La questione del Machiavelli. Quaderni della ‘Critica’ 14 (5): 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Del Lucchese, F. (2011) Conflict, Power, and Multitude in Machiavelli and Spinoza. Tumult and Indignation. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galli, C. (2009) Contingenza e necessità nella ragione politica moderna. Bari, Italy: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentillet, I. (1576) Discours sur les moyens de bien gouverner (Anti-Machiavel) et maintenir en bonne paix un royaume ou autre principauté, divisé en trois parties, a savoir, du Conseil, de la Religion & de la Police que doit tenir un Prince – Contre Nicolas Machiavel. Genève, Switzerland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, S. (2000) Toward a postmodern prince? The battle in Seattle as a moment in the new politics of globalisation. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 29 (1): 131–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gramsci, A. (1992) Brief notes on Machiavelli’s politics. In: Q. Hoare and G.N. Owell Smith (eds.) Selections From the Prison Notebooks. New York: International Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F . (2003) Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoadley, C. (2001) Machiavelli, a man of ‘his’ time: R.B.J. Walker and The Prince. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 30 (1): 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1651) The Leviathan or, The Matter, Form, and Power of a Common-Wealth Ecclesiastical and Civil. London: Andrew Crooke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, D. (2013) Why Hans Morgenthau was not a critical theorist (and why contemporary IR realists should care). International Relations 27 (1): 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machiavelli, N. (1882) Discourses on the first ten books of Titus Livius. In: C. E. Detmold (ed.) The Historical, Political, and Diplomatic Writings of Niccolò Machiavelli, Vol. II. Boston, MA: James R. Osgood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machiavelli, N. (1979) The private letters. In: P. Bondanella and M. Musa (eds.) The Portable Machiavelli. London: Penguin, pp. 53–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machiavelli, N. (1988) The Prince. In: Q. Skinner and R. Price (eds.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machiavelli, N. (2005) The Prince. In: P. Bodanella (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinecke, F. (1924) Die Idee der Staatsräson in der Neueren Geschichte. München und Berlin, Germany: Druck und Verlag von R. Oldenbourg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molloy, S. (2013) ‘Spinoza, Carr, and the ethics of the Twenty years’ crisis. Review of International Studies 39 (2): 251–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritter, G. (1947) Die Dämonie der Macht. Betrachtungen über Geschichte und Wesen des Machtproblems im politischen Denken der Neuzeit. Stuttgart, Germany: Hannsmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1990) Politik und moral. In: M.S. Frings (ed.) Schriften aus dem Nachlass. Gesammelte Werke, Band IV. Philosophie und Geschichte. Bonn, Germany: Bouvier Verlag, pp. 7–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, C. (2007) The Concept of the Political. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Q. (1978) The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Vol. 1: The Renaissance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. (1978) Thoughts on Machiavelli. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vatter, M.E. (2000) Between Form and Event: Machiavelli’s Theory of Political Freedom. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viroli, M. (2010) Machiavelli’s God. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voegelin, E. (1998) History of Political Ideas. Vol. IV. Renaissance and Reformation. Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. (1989) The prince and ‘the pauper’: Tradition, modernity, and practice in the theory of international relations. In: J. Der Derian and M. J. Shapiro (eds.) International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics. New York: Lexington Books, pp. 25–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. (1993) Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, K. (2001) Man, the State and War. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1949) The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight, M. (1994) International Theory: The Three Traditions. Leicester, UK: Leicester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight, M. (2004) Four Seminal Thinkers in International Theory: Machiavelli, Grotius, Kant, and Mazzini. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, M. (2014) Fortuna e ironia in politica. Soveria Mannelli, Italy: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This Special Issue follows and expands on three panels on ‘Machiavelli and International Relations’ which we convened in June 2014 as part of the 39th BISA Annual Conference in Dublin, Ireland. Our thanks go to all the authors for their contributions and interest in the project, without which this Special Issue would have never seen the light of the day. The authors also owe thanks and gratitude, for their intellectual engagement and friendly presence, to Bianca Baggiarini, Elisabetta Brighi, Dhruv Jain, Alexandros Koutsoukis, Seán Molloy, Gabriella Slomp and Swati Srivastava. They are the most grateful to the then convenor of CRIPT (BISA Working Group on Contemporary Research on International Political Theory) Kamila Stullerova for her extraordinary support and kindness, Brian Rosebury for his insightful comments on the Introduction, and Professor Michael Cox for believing in this project from the beginning.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonio Cerella.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cerella, A., Gallo, E. Machiavelli reloaded: Perceptions and misperceptions of the ‘Prince of realism’. Int Polit 53, 435–446 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2016.8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2016.8

Keywords

Navigation